Berkeley's Philosophy PDF

Summary

This document discusses George Berkeley's philosophy, focusing on his response to Locke's empiricism and his ideas on scepticism and idealism, particularly his claim that to be is to be perceived (esse est percipi).

Full Transcript

‭ ERKELEY (1685–1753) The immediate prompt for George Berkeley’s philosophy is Locke.‬ B ‭Berkeley agreed with Locke’s empiricism, but could not accept his fudge over the scepticism‬ ‭that arises because of the ‘veil of perception’ theory – the theory that our ideas are‬ ‭intermediaries between o...

‭ ERKELEY (1685–1753) The immediate prompt for George Berkeley’s philosophy is Locke.‬ B ‭Berkeley agreed with Locke’s empiricism, but could not accept his fudge over the scepticism‬ ‭that arises because of the ‘veil of perception’ theory – the theory that our ideas are‬ ‭intermediaries between ourselves and a world that lies otherwise inaccessibly behind them‬ ‭[behind our ideas] and causes them [causes our ideas]. Berkeley was born at his family’s home,‬ ‭Dysart Castle, in County Kilkenny in Ireland, and educated at Trinity College, Dublin. He took‬ ‭orders in the Church of Ireland and later became Bishop of Cloyne. As these facts show he was‬ ‭a member of the ‘Protestant Ascendancy’, the English-descended ruling elite. [The Church of‬ ‭Ireland is an Anglican church, Anglicanism being a Protestant denomination, though Ireland has‬ ‭remained since the Protestant Reformation a predominantly Catholic country.] His major‬ ‭philosophical works were written early in life; his Principles of Human Knowledge was published‬ ‭in 1710 and his Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, written to address the‬ ‭incomprehension that had greeted the Principles, in 1713. He published treatises on vision,‬ ‭motion and medicine later, but these two works contain his enduring philosophical contribution.‬ ‭The contemporary reaction to Berkeley’s Principles was that his views were neither refutable nor‬ ‭believable. He is still either misunderstood or ignored by some philosophers, even though he is‬ ‭an influence on two twentieth-century schools of thought that will be met with later in these‬ ‭pages, positivism and phenomenalism. Berkeley’s philosophical view is often described as‬ ‭‘immaterialism’, by which is meant a denial of the existence of matter (or, more precisely, [a‬ ‭denial of the existence of] material substance). But he also, famously, argued in support of three‬ ‭further theses. He argued for idealism, the thesis that mind constitutes the ultimate reality. He‬ ‭argued that the existence of [so-called material] things consists in their being perceived: esse‬ ‭est percipi. [This Latin phrase literally means: To be is to be perceived.] And he argued that the‬ ‭mind which is the substance of the world is a single infinite mind – in short, God. These are four‬ ‭different theses, but they are intimately connected, the arguments for the first three sharing most‬ ‭of their premises and steps. Berkeley’s aim in arguing for these theses was to refute two kinds‬ ‭of scepticism. One is epistemological scepticism, which says that we cannot know the true‬ ‭nature of things because of the perceptual and psychological contingencies that oblige us to‬ ‭distinguish appearance from reality in such a way that the latter [reality] lies [perpetually] hidden‬ ‭behind the former [behind appearance—or behind appearances], so that knowledge of it‬ ‭[knowledge of reality] is at least problematic and at worst impossible. 2 The other is theological‬ ‭scepticism, which Berkeley called ‘atheism’ and which in his view included not only denials of‬ ‭the existence of a deity, but also ‘deism’, the view that although the universe might have been‬ ‭created by a deity, it continues to exist without a deity’s active presence. [Deism is the view that‬ ‭God created the world but after that doesn’t do anything to control or determine what goes on in‬ ‭the world—that the physical world is like a machine created by God but which subsequently‬ ‭runs or operates entirely on its own, according to its own internal principles, the so-called laws‬ ‭of nature, so that everything that happens in the world, such the revolving of the planets around‬ ‭the sun or the occurrence of rainstorms, are to be explained scientifically or “mechanically,”‬ ‭rather than as due to God’s will or intervention. In other words, according to deism, God‬ ‭designed and created the world but does not run it or take any further action to cause whatever‬ ‭happens in the world to happen.] In opposing the first scepticism Berkeley took himself to be‬ ‭defending common sense and eradicating ‘causes of error and difficulty in the sciences’. In‬ ‭opposing the second he took himself to be defending religion. Berkeley took the root of‬ ‭ cepticism to be the opening of a gap between experience and the world, forced by theories of‬ s ‭ideas like Locke’s which involve ‘supposing a twofold existence of the objects of sense, the one‬ ‭intelligible, or in the mind, the other real and without [i.e. outside] the mind’. Scepticism arises‬ ‭because ‘for so long as men thought that real things subsisted without [outside] the mind, and‬ ‭that their knowledge was only so far forth real as it was conformable to real things, it follows,‬ ‭they could not be certain they had any real knowledge at all. For how can it be known, that the‬ ‭things which are perceived, are conformable to those which are not perceived, or exist outside‬ ‭the mind?’ The nub of the problem is that if we are acquainted only with our own perceptions,‬ ‭and never with the things which are supposed to lie beyond them, how can we hope for‬ ‭knowledge of those things, or even be justified in asserting their existence? Berkeley’s‬ ‭predecessors talked, as Locke had done, of qualities inhering in matter and causing ideas in us‬ ‭which represent or even resemble those qualities. Matter or material substance is the technical‬ ‭metaphysical concept denoting a supposed corporeal basis underlying the qualities of things.‬ ‭Berkeley was especially troubled by the unempiricist character of this view. If we are to be‬ ‭consistent in our empiricist principles, he asked, how can we tolerate the concept of something‬ ‭which by definition is empirically undetectable, lying hidden behind the perceptible qualities of‬ ‭things as their supposed basis? If the claim (that matter is the substance underlying things)‬ ‭cannot be defended, we have to look elsewhere. [In other words, Berkeley is attacking the view,‬ ‭which Locke upheld, that an object with qualities or properties, such as a piece of paper having‬ ‭qualities like color and shape, can be understood as a material substance in which its qualities‬ ‭of color, shape, size, etc., inhere—according to Berkeley, an object of sensory perception, such‬ ‭as a piece of paper, is nothing more than a bundle or collection of 3 perceptible or “sense”‬ ‭qualities, not some sort of “substance” that exists “behind” its perceivable qualities and in which‬ ‭those qualities “inhere.”] Berkeley’s answer is provided by his answer to scepticism itself. This‬ ‭answer is to deny that there is a gap between [subjective] experience and the [objective] world –‬ ‭in his and Locke’s terminology: between ideas and things – by asserting that things are ideas.‬ ‭The argument is stated with admirable concision in the first six paragraphs of the Principles, its‬ ‭conclusion being the first sentence of paragraph 7: ‘From what has been said, it follows, that‬ ‭there is not any other substance than spirit [or mind], or that which perceives’ (‘spirit’ and ‘mind’‬ ‭are the same thing for Berkeley). All the rest of the Principles and Three Dialogues consists in‬ ‭expansion, clarification and defence of this thesis. The argument is as follows. Berkeley begins‬ ‭in Lockean fashion by offering an inventory of the ‘objects of human knowledge’. They are‬ ‭‘either ideas actually imprinted on the senses, or such as are perceived by attending to the‬ ‭passions and operations of the mind, or lastly ideas formed by help of memory and imagination,‬ ‭either compounding, dividing, or barely representing those originally perceived in the aforesaid‬ ‭ways’. Ideas of sense – colours, shapes and the rest – are ‘observed to accompany each other’‬ ‭in certain ways; ‘collections’ of them ‘come to be marked by one name, and so to be reputed‬ ‭one thing’, for example an apple or a tree. Besides these ideas there is ‘something which knows‬ ‭or perceives them’; this ‘perceiving, active being is what I call mind, spirit, soul or myself’, and it‬ ‭is ‘entirely distinct’ from the ideas it perceives. Thoughts, feelings and imaginings exist only in‬ ‭the mind. But so also do the ideas of things – which, remember, are collections of ideas: the‬ ‭idea of an apple is a composite of ideas of the colours, shapes and tastes that constitute it. So it‬ ‭is no less evident that the various sensations or ideas imprinted on the sense [or on the‬ ‭senses], however blended or combined together (that is, whatever objects they compose),‬ ‭ annot exist otherwise than in a mind perceiving them. From these claims it follows that the gap‬ c ‭between things and ideas vanishes; for if things are collections of qualities, and qualities are‬ ‭sensible ideas, and sensible ideas exist only in the mind, then what it is for a thing to exist is for‬ ‭it to be perceived – in Berkeley’s phrase: to be is to be perceived: esse est percipi. ‘For as to‬ ‭what is said of the absolute [i.e. mind-independent] existence of unthinking things [i.e. ideas or‬ ‭collections of ideas] without any relation to their being perceived, that seems perfectly‬ ‭unintelligible. Their esse is percipi, nor is it possible that they should have any existence, out of‬ ‭the minds or thinking things which perceive them.’ 4 Berkeley knows that this claim is surprising,‬ ‭so he remarks that although people think that sensible [or perceptible] objects like mountains‬ ‭and houses have an ‘absolute’, that is, perception-independent, existence, reflection on the‬ ‭points just made show that this is a contradiction. ‘For what’, he asks, ‘are the aforementioned‬ ‭[perceptible] objects but the things we perceive by sense, and what do we perceive besides our‬ ‭own ideas or sensations; and is it not plainly repugnant [illogical, contradictory] that any of these‬ ‭or any combination of them should exist unperceived?’ A point that requires immediate‬ ‭emphasis is that this argument, together with Berkeley’s correlative denial of the existence of‬ ‭material substance, is not a denial of the existence of the external world and the physical‬ ‭objects it contains, such as tables and chairs, mountains and trees. Nor does Berkeley hold that‬ ‭the world exists only because it is thought of by any one or more finite minds, such as yours or‬ ‭mine. In one sense of the term ‘realist’...Berkeley is a realist, in holding that the existence of the‬ ‭physical world is independent of finite minds, individually or collectively. What he argues instead‬ ‭is that its existence is not independent of mind as such. The source of the belief that things can‬ ‭exist apart from perception of them [according to Betkeley] is the doctrine of ‘abstract ideas’,‬ ‭which Berkeley attacks in his Introduction to the Principles. Abstraction consists in separating‬ ‭things which can be separated only in thought, not in reality, for example the colour and the‬ ‭extension of a surface; or which involves noting a feature common to many different things, and‬ ‭attending only to that feature and not to its particular instances – in this way we arrive at the‬ ‭‘abstract idea’ of, say, Redness, apart from any particular red object. Abstraction is a falsifying‬ ‭move [according to Berkeley]; what prompts the ‘common opinion’ about houses and mountains‬ ‭is that we abstract existence from perception, and so come to believe that things can exist‬ ‭unperceived. But because things are ideas, and because ideas exist only if perceived by minds,‬ ‭the notion of ‘absolute existence outside mind’ is a contradiction. So, says Berkeley, to say that‬ ‭things exist is to say that they are perceived, and therefore ‘so long as they are not perceived by‬ ‭me, or do not exist in my mind or that of any created spirit, they must either have no existence‬ ‭at all, or else subsist in the mind of some eternal spirit.’ And from this the conclusion follows that‬ ‭‘there is not any other substance than spirit, or that which perceives.’ The argument in sum is‬ ‭therefore this: the things we encounter in episodes of perceptual experience – apples, stones,‬ ‭trees – are collections of ‘ideas’. Ideas are the immediate objects of awareness. To exist they‬ ‭must be perceived; they cannot exist ‘without (independently of) mind’. Therefore mind is the‬ ‭substance of the world. Berkeley is a rigorous empiricist; we are not entitled to assert, believe or‬ ‭regard as meaningful anything not justified by experience. To deny that there is a ‘seems–is’ 5‬ ‭distinction [in other words, to deny that there is a distinction between appearances and a reality‬ ‭that stands behind the appearances and exists independently of any and all appearances] is‬ ‭just another way of asserting that sensible objects (things in the world) are collections of‬ ‭sensible [or sense] qualities, and hence of ideas. This shows that the concept of matter is‬ r‭ edundant, Berkeley claims, because everything required to explain the world and experience of‬ ‭it is available in recognizing that minds and ideas are all there can be...-‬

Use Quizgecko on...
Browser
Browser