Summa Theologica - Law - Question 90 - PDF

Loading...
Loading...
Loading...
Loading...
Loading...
Loading...
Loading...

Document Details

MasterfulRationality999

Uploaded by MasterfulRationality999

College of Southern Nevada

2011

Thomas Aquinas

Tags

Moral philosophy Legal theory Summa Theologica Political philosophy

Summary

This document contains a section from the Summa Theologica, focusing on the nature of law. It discusses whether law belongs to reason, if all laws are ordained for the common good, and if any person is capable of creating law. The text provides arguments and counterarguments for each point raised, referencing authorities like Aristotle and the Apostle.

Full Transcript

SUMMA THEOLOGICA LAW said before. For it belongs to reason to order us to our end, which is the primary source regarding our...

SUMMA THEOLOGICA LAW said before. For it belongs to reason to order us to our end, which is the primary source regarding our prospective action, as the Philosopher says. And the ST I–II source in any kind of thing is the measure and rule of that kind of thing (e.g., units in numbers and first QUESTION 90 movements in movements). And so we conclude that law belongs to reason. On the Essence of Law Reply Obj. 1. We say that law, since it is a rule or measure, belongs to something in two ways. It belongs FIRST ARTICLE in one way as to what measures and rules. And law Does Law Belong to Reason? in this way belongs only to reason, since measuring We thus proceed to the first inquiry. It seems that law and ruling belong to reason. Law belongs to some- does not belong to reason, for the following reasons: thing in a second way as to what is ruled and mea- Objection 1. The Apostle in Rom. 7:23 says: “I sured. And then law applies to everything that a law perceive another law in my bodily members,” etc. induces to something, so that we can call every incli- But nothing belonging to reason belongs to bodily nation resulting from a law, law by participation, as members, since reason does not use bodily organs. it were, not essentially. And we in this way call the Therefore, law does not belong to reason. very inclination of bodily members to concupiscence Obj. 2. Only power, habits, and acts belong to rea- the law of the bodily members. son. But law is not the very power of reason. Likewise, Reply Obj. 2. Regarding external acts, we can con- law is not a habit of reason, since habits of reason are sider the activity and the product of the activity (e.g., intellectual virtues, about which I have spoken before. building and the building constructed). Just so, re- Nor is law an act of reason, since law would cease when garding acts of reason, we can consider the very acts the lawmaker ceased to reason (e.g., when he is sleep- of reason (i.e., acts of understanding and reasoning) ing). Therefore, law does not belong to reason. and the things produced by such acts. And regarding Obj. 3. Law induces those subject to the law to theoretical reason, definitions are indeed the first act rightly. But inducing to act rightly belongs in the product. Propositions are the second product. And strict sense to the will, as is evident from what I have syllogisms and arguments the third product. And prac- said before. Therefore, law belongs to the will rather tical reason also uses a kind of syllogism regarding than to reason, as the Jurist also says: “The pleasure prospective actions, as I have maintained before, and of the ruler has the force of law.” as the Philosopher teaches in the Ethics. Therefore, On the contrary, it belongs to law to command and there are things in practical reason that are related forbid. But to command belongs to reason, as I have to actions as propositions in theoretical reason are maintained before. Therefore, law belongs to reason. related to conclusions. And such universal proposi- I answer that law is a rule and measure of acts that tions of practical reason related to actions have the induces persons to act or refrain from acting. For nature of law. And reason indeed sometimes actually law [Lat.: lex] is derived from binding [Lat.: ligare] contemplates and sometimes only habitually retains because law obliges persons to act. And the rule and these propositions. measure of human acts is reason, which is the primary Reply Obj. 3. Reason has from the will the power source of human acts, as is evident from what I have to induce activity, as I have said before, since reason 463 464 AQUINAS commands means because one wills ends. But an act and political community. For he says in the Ethics of reason needs to rule the will regarding the means that “we call those laws just that constitute and pre- commanded in order that the willing have the nature serve happiness and its particulars by citizens’ sharing of law. And we in this way understand that the will in a political community.” For the political commu- of a ruler has the force of law. Otherwise, the will- nity is the perfect community, as he says in the Pol- ing of the ruler would be injustice rather than law. itics. And regarding any kind of thing, the one most such SECOND ARTICLE is the source of the others, and we call the others Is Law Always Ordained for the such by their relation to that one. For example, fire, Common Good? which is hottest, causes heat in composite material substances, which we call hot insofar as they share We thus proceed to the second inquiry. It seems that in fire. And so, since we speak of law in the first place law is not ordained for the common good as its end, because of its ordination to the common good, every for the following reasons: other precept regarding particular acts has the nature Objection 1. It belongs to law to command and of law only because of its ordination to the common forbid. But precepts are ordained for particular goods. good. And so every law is ordained for the com- Therefore, the end of law is not always the com- mon good. mon good. Reply Obj. 1. Precepts signify the application of Obj. 2. Law directs the actions of human beings. laws to things regulated by the laws. And the ordina- But human acts regard particulars. Therefore, law is tion to the common good, which belongs to law, can likewise ordained for particular goods. be applied to particular ends. And so there can be Obj. 3. Isidore says in his Etymologies: “If law is precepts even regarding particular matters. based on reason, everything founded on reason will Reply Obj. 2. Actions indeed concern particular be law.” But both things ordained for the common matters, but such particulars can be related to the good and things ordained for private good are based common good by sharing in the final cause, insofar on reason. Therefore, law is ordained both for the as we call the common good the final cause, not by common good and for the private good of individuals. sharing in a genus or species. On the contrary, Isidore says in his Etymologies Reply Obj. 3. As theoretical reason firmly estab- that laws are “enacted for no private convenience but lishes nothing except by tracing things back to first for the common benefit of citizens.” indemonstrable principles, so practical reason firmly I answer that as I have said, law belongs to the establishes nothing except by ordering things to our source of human acts, since law is their rule and ultimate end, that is, our common good. And what measure. And as reason is the source of human acts, reason so establishes has the nature of law. so also is there in reason itself something that is the source of all other kinds of acts. And so law needs chiefly and especially to belong to this source. THIRD ARTICLE And the first source in practical matters, with which Is Any Person’s Reason Competent to practical reason is concerned, is the ultimate end. Make Law? But the ultimate end of human life is happiness or blessedness, as I have maintained before. And so law We thus proceed to the third inquiry. It seems that especially needs to regard the ordination to bless- any person’s reason is competent to make law, for the edness. following reasons: Moreover, law in the strict sense needs to concern Objection 1. The Apostle says in Rom. 2:14 that ordination to happiness in general, since every part “when the Gentiles, who do not have the law, by is related to a whole as something imperfect to some- nature do the things the law prescribes, they make law thing perfect. And so also the Philosopher, regarding for themselves.” But we say the same about everybody. the cited definition of laws, speaks of both happiness Therefore, anyone can make law for oneself. Summa Theologica, Law, Question 90 465 Obj. 2. As the Philosopher says in the Ethics, “law- good of a household is ordained for the good of a makers aim to induce human beings to virtue.” But political community, which is a perfect community. any human being can lead others to virtue. Therefore, And so those who govern households can indeed the reason of any human being is competent to make precepts and rules, but such precepts and rules make law. do not have the nature of law in the strict sense. Obj. 3. As the ruler of a political community gov- erns that community, so the head of a household FOURTH ARTICLE governs his household. But the ruler of a political Is Promulgation an Essential Component community can make laws regarding the political of Law? community. Therefore, any head of a household can make laws regarding his household. We thus proceed to the fourth inquiry. It seems that On the contrary, Isidore says in his Etymologies, promulgation is not an essential component of law, and the Decretum maintains: “Laws are ordinances for the following reasons: of the people whereby elders and commoners together Objection 1. The natural law most has the nature prescribe things.” Therefore, not every person’s reason of law. But the natural law does not need to be prom- is competent to make law. ulgated. Therefore, promulgation is not an essential I answer that law in the strict sense primarily and component of law. chiefly regards ordaining things for the common Obj. 2. Obligation to do or not to do things belongs good. But ordaining things for the common good in the strict sense to law. But both those to whom belongs either to the whole people or to persons acting laws have been promulgated and those to whom laws in the name of the whole people. And so lawmaking have not, are obliged to obey laws. Therefore, promul- belongs either to the whole people or to a public gation is not an essential component of law. personage who has the care of the whole people. For Obj. 3. The obligation to obey laws also extends also in all other matters, ordaining things for ends to the future, since “laws impose obligation regarding belongs to those to whom the ends belong. future affairs,” as the Code says. But laws are promul- Reply Obj. 1. As I have said before law belongs gated to those present at their promulgation. There- both to those who rule, and by participation to those fore, promulgation is not an essential component who are ruled. And it is in the latter way that everyone of law. makes law for oneself, as one participates in the ordi- On the contrary, the Decretum says that “laws are nations of the ruler. And so also the Apostle adds in established when they are promulgated.” v. 15: “And they manifest the law’s operation written I answer that laws are imposed on others as rules in their hearts.” and measures, as I have said. But rules and measures Reply Obj. 2. Private persons cannot effectively are imposed by being applied to those ruled and induce others to virtue. For private persons can only measured. And so laws, in order to oblige persons, as offer advice and have no coercive power if their advice is proper to law, need to be applied to those who are should not be accepted. And law should have coercive to be ruled by the laws. But the promulgation leading power in order to induce others effectively to virtue, them to knowledge achieves such application. And as the Philosopher says in the Ethics. But the people so promulgation is necessary for laws to be in force. or a public personage has such coercive power and And so we can compose the definition of law from the right to inflict punishment, as I shall explain later. the four characteristics I have mentioned: law is an And so it belongs only to the people or a public ordination of reason for the common good by one personage to make law. who has the care of the community, and promulgated. Reply Obj. 3. As human beings are parts of a Reply Obj. 1. The natural law is promulgated by household, so households are parts of a political com- God when he implants it in the minds of human munity, as the Politics says. And so, as the good of a beings so that they know it by nature. human being is not the ultimate end of that individual Reply Obj. 2. Those to whom a law is not promul- but is ordained for the common good, so also the gated are obliged to observe it insofar as others make 466 AQUINAS it known to them, or it can become known to them nonexisting things into existence.” Therefore, the after it has been promulgated. eternal conception of God’s law has the nature of an Reply Obj. 3. The present promulgation of a law eternal law insofar as he ordains that law for gover- reaches into the future through the durability of writ- nance of the world he foreknows. ten words, which in a way are always promulgating Reply Obj. 2. Word and inscription promulgate it. And so Isidore says in his Etymologies that “we law. And God promulgates his eternal law in both derive law [Lat.: lex] from reading [Lat.: legere], since ways, since the Word of God and the inscription of law is written.” the predestined in the Book of Life are eternal. But as regards the creatures who hear or read God’s law, QUESTION 91 the promulgation cannot be eternal. Reply Obj. 3. Law signifies actively ordaining things for an end, namely, that law ordain things for On Different Kinds of Law an end. And law does not signify being ordained for an end, that is, that law itself be ordained for another FIRST ARTICLE end, except incidentally in the case of human rulers, Is There an Eternal Law? whose end is extrinsic to themselves. And then the We thus proceed to the first inquiry. It seems that rulers’ laws also need to be ordained for that extrinsic there is no eternal law, for the following reasons: end. But the end of God’s governance is God himself, Objection 1. Every law is imposed on particular and his law is indistinguishable from himself. And so persons. But there was no one from eternity on whom the eternal law is not ordained for another end. law could be imposed, since only God was from eternity. Therefore, no law is eternal. SECOND ARTICLE Obj. 2. Promulgation is an essential component Is There a Natural Law in Us? of law. But there could be no promulgation from We thus proceed to the second inquiry. It seems that eternity, since there was no one from eternity to whom there is no natural law in us, for the following reasons: a law would be be promulgated. Therefore, no law Objection 1. The eternal law sufficiently governs can be eternal. human beings. For Augustine says in his work On Obj. 3. Law signifies the direction to an end. But Free Choice that “the eternal law is that whereby it nothing ordained to an end is eternal, since only the is right that all things be most orderly.” But nature ultimate end is eternal. Therefore, no law is eternal. does not abound in superfluities, nor is it wanting in On the contrary, Augustine says in his work On necessities. Therefore, there is no natural law for Free Choice: “No one with intelligence can perceive human beings. the law called supreme reason not to be immutable Obj. 2. Law ordains human beings to their end and eternal.” regarding their actions, as I have maintained before. I answer that as I have said before, law is simply But nature does not ordain human actions to their a dictate of practical reason by a ruler who governs end, as happens in the case of irrational creatures, a perfect community. But supposing that God’s provi- which act for their ends only by natural appetites. dence rules the world, as I maintained in the First Rather, human beings act for their end by the use of Part, his reason evidently governs the entire commu- their reason and will. Therefore, there is no natural nity of the universe. And so the plan of governance law for human beings. of the world existing in God as the ruler of the universe Obj. 3. The freer one is, the less one is subject to has the nature of law. And since God’s reason con- law. But human beings are freer than all other animals ceives eternally, as Prov. 8:23 says, not temporally, because human beings, unlike other animals, have we need to say that such law is eternal. free choice. Therefore, since other animals are not Reply Obj. 1. Things that do not exist in them- subject to a natural law, neither are human beings. selves exist with God insofar as he foreknows and On the contrary, a gloss on Rom. 2:14, “When the foreordains them, as Rom. 4:17 says: “And he calls Gentiles, who do not have the law, do by nature Summa Theologica, Law, Question 91 467 things prescribed by the law,” etc., says: “Although have said before. And irrational creatures do not they do not have the written law, they have a natural share in the eternal law by the use of reason. And law, whereby each of them understands and is con- so we can call the latter participation law only scious of good and evil.” by analogy. I answer that as I have said before, law, since it is a rule or measure, can belong to things in two ways: THIRD ARTICLE in one way to those who rule and measure; in a Are There Human Laws? second way to those ruled and measured, since things are ruled or measured insofar as they partake of the We thus proceed to the third inquiry. It seems that rule or measure. But the eternal law rules and mea- there are no human laws, for the following reasons: sures everything subject to God’s providence, as is Objection. 1. The natural law shares in the eternal evident from what I have said before. And so every- law, as I have said. But the eternal law “renders all thing evidently shares in some way in the eternal law, things most orderly,” as Augustine says in his work namely, insofar as all things have inclinations to their On Free Choice. Therefore, the natural law suffices own acts and ends from its imprint on them. But the for ordering all human affairs. Therefore, there is no rational creature is subject to God’s providence in a need for human laws. more excellent way than other things, since such a Obj. 2. Law has the nature of a measure, as I have creature also shares in God’s providence in providing said. But human reason is not the measure of things. for itself and others. And so it shares in the eternal plan Rather, the converse is true, as the Metaphysics says. whereby it has its natural inclination to its requisite Therefore, human reason can produce no law. activity and end. And we call such participation in Obj. 3. A measure should be most certain, as the the eternal law by rational creatures the natural law. Metaphysics says. But dictates of human reason about And so Ps. 4:6, after saying, “Offer just sacrifices,” things to be done are uncertain, as Wis. 9:14 says: asks: “Who shows us just things?” and replies: “The “The thoughts of mortal human beings are fraught light of your countenance, O Lord, has been inscribed with fear, and our foresight uncertain.” Therefore, on us.” The Psalmist thus signifies that the light of human reason cannot produce laws. natural reason whereby we discern good and evil is On the contrary, Augustine in his work On Free simply the imprint of God’s light in us. And so it is Choice posits two kinds of law, one kind eternal, and clear that the natural law is simply rational creatures’ the other temporal, which he calls human. participation in the eternal law. I answer that law is a dictate of practical reason, Reply Obj. 1. The argument of this objection as I have said before. But there are similar processes would be valid if the natural law were to be something of practical and theoretical reason, since both proceed different from the eternal law. But the natural law from principles to conclusions, as I have maintained shares in the eternal law, as I have said. before. Therefore, we should say that we advance in Reply Obj. 2. Every activity of reason and the will theoretical reason from indemonstrable first princi- in us is derived from what exists by nature, as I have ples, naturally known, to the conclusions of different maintained before, since every process of reasoning sciences, conclusions not implanted in us by nature is derived from first principles known by nature, and but discovered by exercising reason. Just so, human every desire of means is derived from the natural reason needs to advance from the precepts of the desire of our ultimate end. And so also the natural natural law, as general and indemonstrable first prin- law needs first to direct our acts to their end. ciples, to matters that are to be more particularly Reply Obj. 3. Even irrational animals, like ratio- regulated. And we call such regulations devised by nal creatures, share in the eternal law in their own human reason human laws, provided that the other way. But because rational creatures share in the conditions belonging to the nature of law are ob- eternal law by using their intellect and reason, we served, as I have said before. And so also Cicero says call their participation in the eternal law law in in his Rhetoric: “Human law originally sprang from the strict sense, since law belongs to reason, as I nature. Then things became customs because of their 468 AQUINAS rational benefit. Then fear and reverence for law are human laws, as I have said. Therefore, human validated things that both sprang from nature and beings do not need to be governed by another di- were approved by custom.” vine law. Reply Obj. 1. Human reason cannot partake of the Obj. 3. Human nature is more self-sufficient than complete dictates of God’s reason but partakes of irrational creatures. But irrational creatures have no them in its own way and incompletely. And so regard- divine law besides the inclinations that nature im- ing theoretical reason, we by our natural participation plants in them. Therefore, much less should rational in God’s wisdom know general principles but do not creatures have a divine law besides the natural law. specifically know every truth, as God’s wisdom does. On the contrary, David petitioned God to lay out Just so regarding practical reason, human beings by the law before him, saying in Ps. 119:33: “Teach me nature partake of the eternal law as to general princi- the law, O Lord, in the way of your statutes.” ples but not as to particular specifications of particular I answer that in addition to the natural law and matters, although such specifications belong to the human laws, divine law was necessary to give direc- eternal law. And so human reason needs to proceed tion to human life. And there are four reasons for this. further to determine the particular prescriptions of First, indeed, law directs our acts in relation to our human law. ultimate end. And human beings, if they were indeed Reply Obj. 2. Human reason as such is not the ordained only for an end that did not surpass the rule of things, but the first principles implanted by proportion of their natural ability, would not, regard- nature in human reason are the general rules or mea- ing reason, need to have any direction superior to sures of everything related to human conduct. And the natural law and human laws derived from the natural reason is the rule and measure of such things, natural law. But because human beings are ordained although not of things from nature. for the end of eternal blessedness, which surpasses Reply Obj. 3. Practical reason regards practical their proportional natural human capacity, as I have matters, which are particular and contingent, and maintained before, God needed to lay down a law does not regard necessary things, as theoretical reason superior to the natural law and human laws to direct does. And so human laws cannot have the absolute human beings to their end. certainty of demonstrated scientific conclusions. Nor Second, because of the uncertainty of human judg- need every measure be unerring and certain in every ment, especially regarding contingent and particular respect. Rather, every measure needs to be such only matters, different persons may judge differently about to the extent possible in its kind of thing. various human actions, and so even different and contrary laws result. Therefore, in order that human FOURTH ARTICLE beings can know beyond any doubt what they should Did Human Beings Need a Divine Law? do or should not do, a divinely revealed law, regarding which error is impossible, was needed to direct hu- We thus proceed to the fourth inquiry. It seems that man beings in their actions. human beings did not need any divine law, for the Third, human beings can make laws regarding following reasons: things they are able to judge. But human beings can Objection 1. The natural law is our participation judge only sensibly perceptible external acts, not hid- in the eternal law, as I have said. But eternal law is den internal movements. And yet human beings need divine law, as I have said. Therefore, we do not need to live righteously regarding both kinds of acts in order another divine law besides the natural law and the to attain complete virtue. And so human laws could not human laws derived from natural law. prohibit or adequately ordain internal acts, and divine Obj. 2. Sir. 15:14 says that “God left human beings law needed to supplement human laws. in the hands of their own deliberation.” But delibera- Fourth, human laws cannot punish or prohibit all tion is an act of reason, as I have maintained before. evil deeds, as Augustine says in his work On Free Therefore, God left human beings to the governance Choice. This is because in seeking to eliminate all of their own reason. But the dictates of human reason evils, one would thereby also take away many goods Summa Theologica, Law, Question 94 469 and not benefit the common good necessary for hu- resis is a habit, as I maintained in the First Part. man companionship. Therefore, in order that no evil Therefore, the natural law is a habit. remain unforbidden or unpunished, there needed to Obj. 3. The natural law always abides in human be a divine law forbidding all sins. beings, as I shall make clear later. But human beings’ And Ps. 19:7 touches on these four reasons when reason, to which that law belongs, is not always think- it says: “The law of the Lord is pure,” that is, permit- ing about the natural law. Therefore, the natural law ting no sinful wickedness; “converting souls,” since is a habit, not an act. it directs both external and internal acts; “the Lord’s On the contrary, Augustine says in his work On faithful witness” because of its certain truth and recti- the Marital Good that “habits are the means whereby tude; “offering wisdom to the little ones,” since it we do things when we need to.” But the natural law ordains human beings for a supernatural and di- is not such, since that law belongs to infants and the vine end. damned, who cannot act by reason of its presence. Reply Obj. 1. The natural law partakes of the eter- Therefore, the natural law is not a habit. nal law in proportion to the capacity of human nature. I answer that we can speak about habits in two But human beings need to be directed in a higher ways. We speak of them in one way in the strict sense way to their ultimate supernatural end. And so God and essentially, and then the natural law is not a gives an additional law that partakes of the eternal habit. For I have said before that the natural law is law in a higher way. constituted by reason, just as propositions are works Reply Obj. 2. Deliberation is an inquiry, and so of reason. And what one does, and the means whereby deliberation needs to advance from some principles. one does it, are not the same. For example, one makes And it does not suffice that it advance from first princi- a fitting speech by means of the habit of grammar. ples implanted by nature, that is, precepts of the Therefore, since habits are the means whereby one natural law, for the aforementioned reasons. Rather, does things, the natural law cannot be a habit in the other principles, namely, precepts of divine law, need strict sense and essentially. to be supplied. We can speak of habits in a second way as what we Reply Obj. 3. Irrational creatures are not ordained possess by reason of habits. For example, we call faith for higher ends than those proportioned to their natu- what we have by reason of the habit of faith. And so, ral powers. And so the argument of the objection as reason sometimes actually considers precepts of the is inapplicable. natural law and sometimes only habitually possesses them, we can in the latter way say that the natural law QUESTION 94 is a habit. Just so, the indemonstrable first principles in theoretical matters are principles belonging to the habit of first principles, not the very habit. On the Natural Law Reply Obj. 1. The Philosopher in the cited text is attempting to discover the genus of virtues. And since FIRST ARTICLE virtues are evidently sources of activity, he posits only Is the Natural Law a Habit? things that are sources of human activity, namely, We thus proceed to the first inquiry. It seems that the powers, habits, and emotions. But other things belong natural law is a habit, for the following reasons: to the soul besides the latter three. For example, Objection 1. “Three things belong to the soul: pow- certain acts belong to the soul: willing to those willing, ers, habits, and emotions,” as the Philosopher says in and things known to those knowing. And the natural the Ethics. But the natural law is neither a power of properties of the soul, such as immortality and the the soul nor an emotion. Therefore, the natural law like, belong to the soul. is a habit. Reply Obj. 2. Basil calls synderesis the law of our Obj. 2. Basil says that conscience, that is, syndere- intellect insofar as it is the habit that contains the sis, is “the law of our intellect,” and we can only precepts of the natural law, that is, the first principles understand such regarding the natural law. But synde- of human actions. 470 AQUINAS Reply Obj. 3. The argument of this objection first principles of scientific demonstrations are related reaches the conclusion that we possess the natural to theoretical reason. For both the precepts of the law in a habitual way, and we concede this. natural law and the first principles of scientific dem- Qualification to the argument in the section On onstrations are self-evident principles. And we speak the contrary. Sometimes, due to an impediment, of things being self-evident in two ways: in one way one cannot make use of what one possesses habitu- as such; in a second way in relation to ourselves. We ally. For example, human beings cannot make use indeed speak of self-evident propositions as such when of habitual knowledge when they are asleep. And their predicates belong to the nature of their subjects, likewise, children cannot make use of habitual although such propositions may not be self-evident understanding of first principles, or even of the to those who do not know the definition of the sub- natural law, which they possess habitually, due to jects. For example, the proposition “Human beings their immature age. are rational” is by its nature self-evident, since to speak of something human is to speak of something rational, SECOND ARTICLE although the proposition is not self-evident to one Does the Natural Law Include Several who does not know what a human being is. And so, Precepts or Only One? as Boethius says in his work On Groups of Seven, there are axioms or universally self-evident proposi- We thus proceed to the second inquiry. It seems that tions, and propositions whose terms all persons know that the natural law includes only one precept, not (e.g., “Every whole is greater than one of its parts” several, for the following reasons: and “Things equal to the same thing are themselves Objection 1. Law belongs to the genus of precept, equal”) are such. But some propositions are self- as I have maintained before. Therefore, if there evident only to the wise, who understand what the were to be many precepts of the natural law, it proposition’s terms signify. For example, for those who would follow logically that there would also be understand that angels are not material substances, many natural laws. it is self-evident that angels are not circumscriptively Obj. 2. The natural law results from the nature in a place, something not evident to the uneducated, of human beings. But human nature as a whole who do not understand the nature of angels. is one, although multiple regarding its parts. There- And there is a priority regarding the things that fall fore, either there is only one precept of the natural within the understanding of all persons. For what first law because of the unity of the whole, or there falls within our understanding is being, the under- are many precepts because of the many parts of standing of which is included in everything that one human nature. And so even things that regard understands. And so the first indemonstrable princi- inclinations of concupiscible power will need to ple is that one cannot at the same time affirm and belong to the natural law. deny the same thing. And this principle is based on Obj. 3. Law belongs to reason, as I have said before. the nature of being and nonbeing, and all other prin- But there is only one power of reason in human ciples are based on it, as the Metaphysics says. And beings. Therefore, there is only one precept of the as being is the first thing that without qualification natural law. falls within our understanding, so good is the first On the contrary, the precepts of the natural thing that falls within the understanding of practical law in human beings are related to action as the reason. And practical reason is ordered to action, since first principles in scientific matters are related to every efficient cause acts for the sake of an end, which theoretical knowledge. But there are several inde- has the nature of good. And so the first principle in monstrable first principles of theoretical knowledge. practical reason is one based on the nature of good, Therefore, there are also several precepts of the namely, that good is what all things seek. Therefore, natural law. the first precept of the natural law is that we should I answer that as I have said before, the precepts of do and seek good, and shun evil. And all the other the natural law are related to practical reason as the precepts of the natural law are based on that precept, Summa Theologica, Law, Question 94 471 namely, that all the things that practical reason by THIRD ARTICLE nature understands to be human goods or evils belong Do All Virtuous Acts Belong to the to precepts of the natural law as things to be done Natural Law? or shunned. And since good has the nature of end, and evil the We proceed thus to the third inquiry. It seems that nature of the contrary, reason by nature understands not all virtuous acts belong to the natural law, for the to be good all the things for which human beings following reasons: have a natural inclination, and so to be things to be Objection 1. It belongs to the nature of law that actively sought, and understands contrary things as law be ordained for the common good, as I have said evil and to be shunned. Therefore, the ordination of before. But some virtuous acts are ordained for the our natural inclinations ordains the precepts of the private good of an individual, as is particularly evident natural law. in the case of acts of the virtue of moderation. There- First, for example, human beings have an inclina- fore, not all virtuous acts are subject to the natural law. tion for good by the nature they share with all sub- Obj. 2. All sins are contrary to certain virtuous stances, namely, as every substance by nature seeks acts. Therefore, if all virtuous acts belong to the natu- to preserve itself. And regarding this inclination, ral law, it seems that all sins are consequently contrary means that preserve our human life and prevent the to nature. And yet we say this in a special way about contrary belong to the natural law. some sins. Second, human beings have more particular incli- Obj. 3. Everybody agrees about things that are in nations by the nature they share with other animals. accord with nature. But not everybody agrees about And so the Digest says that things “that nature has virtuous acts, for things that are virtuous for some are taught all animals,” such as the sexual union of male vicious for others. Therefore, not all virtuous acts and female, and the upbringing of children, and the belong to the natural law. like, belong to the natural law. On the contrary, Damascene says in his work On Third, human beings have inclinations for good Orthodox Faith that “virtues are natural.” Therefore, by their rational nature, which is proper to them. For virtuous acts are subject to the natural law. example, human beings by nature have inclinations I answer that we can speak about virtuous acts in to know truths about God and to live in society with two ways: in one way as virtuous; in a second way as other human beings. And so things that relate to we consider such acts in their own species. Therefore, such inclinations belong to the natural law (e.g., that if we are speaking about virtuous acts as virtuous, human beings shun ignorance, that they not offend then all virtuous acts belong to the natural law. For those with whom they ought to live sociably, and I have said that everything to which human beings other such things regarding those inclinations). are inclined by their nature belongs to the natural Reply Obj. 1. All the precepts of the natural law, law. But everything is by its nature inclined to the insofar as they relate to one first precept, have the activity that its form renders fitting. For example, fire nature of one natural law. is inclined to heat things. And so, since the rational Reply Obj. 2. All the inclinations of any part of soul is the specific form of human beings, everyone human nature (e.g., the concupiscible and irascible has an inclination from one’s nature to act in accord powers), insofar as reason rules them, belong to the with reason. And this is to act virtuously. And so in natural law and are traced to one first precept, as I this regard, all virtuous acts belong to the natural law, have said. And so there are many precepts of the since one’s own reason by nature dictates that one natural law as such, but they share a common foun- act virtuously. dation. But if we should be speaking about virtuous acts Reply Obj. 3. Reason, although as such one power, as such and such, namely, as we consider them in ordains everything that concerns human beings. And their own species, then not all virtuous acts belong so the law of reason includes everything that reason to the natural law. For we do many things virtuously can rule. to which nature does not at first incline us, but which 472 AQUINAS human beings by the inquiry of reason have discov- before. But nature inclines different human beings to ered to be useful for living righteously. different things. For example, nature inclines some Reply Obj. 1. Moderation concerns the natural to desire pleasures, others to desire honors, others to desires for food and drink and sex, which desires are desire other things. Therefore, the natural law is not indeed ordained for the natural common good, just the same for all human beings. as other prescriptions of the natural law are ordained On the contrary, Isidore says in his Etymologies: for the common moral good. “The natural law is common to all nations.” Reply Obj. 2. We can call the nature proper to I answer that things to which nature inclines hu- human beings the nature of human beings. And so man beings belong to the natural law, as I have said all sins, insofar as they are contrary to reason, are also before, and one of the things proper to human beings contrary to nature, as Damascene makes clear in his is that their nature inclines them to act in accord work On Orthodox Faith. Or else we can call the with reason. And it belongs to reason to advance from nature common to human beings and other animals the general to the particular, as the Physics makes the nature of human beings. And so we speak of clear. And regarding that process, theoretical reason certain particular sins being contrary to nature. For proceeds in one way, and practical reason in another example, the sexual intercourse of males, which we way. For inasmuch as theoretical reason is especially specifically call the sin contrary to nature, is contrary concerned about necessary things, which cannot be to the sexual union of male and female, and such otherwise disposed, its particular conclusions, just like sexual union is natural for all animals. its general principles, are true without exception. But Reply Obj. 3. The argument of this objection is practical reason is concerned about contingent things, valid regarding virtuous acts as such and such. For which include human actions. And so the more reason then, because of the different conditions of human goes from the general to the particular, the more excep- beings, some acts may be virtuous for some persons, tions we find, although there is some necessity in the as proportionate and suitable for them, which are general principles. Therefore, truth in theoretical mat- nonetheless wicked for other persons, as dispropor- ters, both first principles and conclusions, is the same tionate for them. for all human beings, although some know only the truth of the principles, which we call universal proposi- FOURTH ARTICLE tions, and not the truth of the conclusions. But truth Is the Natural Law the Same for All in practical matters, or practical rectitude, is the same Human Beings? for all human beings only regarding the general princi- ples, not regarding the particular conclusions. And not We thus proceed to the fourth inquiry. It seems that all of those with practical rectitude regarding particu- the natural law is not the same for all human beings, lars know the truth in equal measure. for the following reasons: Therefore, the truth or rectitude regarding the gen- Objection 1. The Decretum says that “the natural eral principles of both theoretical and practical reason law is contained in the [Old] Law and the Gospel.” is the same for all persons and known in equal mea- But what is contained in the Law and the Gospel is sure by all of them. And the truth regarding the not in the common possession of all, since Rom. 10:16 particular conclusions of theoretical reason is the says: “Some do not heed the Gospel.” Therefore, the same for all persons, but some know such truth less natural law is not the same for all human beings. than others. For example, it is true for all persons Obj. 2. “We call things in accord with law just,” that triangles have three angles equal to two right as the Ethics says. But the same work says that nothing angles, although not everybody knows this. is so universally just that it is not otherwise for some. But the truth or rectitude regarding particular Therefore, even the natural law is not the same for conclusions of practical reason is neither the same all human beings. for all persons nor known in equal measure even Obj. 3. Things to which human beings’ nature by those for whom it is the same. For example, it inclines them belong to the natural law, as I have said is correct and true for all persons that they should Summa Theologica, Law, Question 94 473 act in accord with reason. And it follows as a Reply Obj. 2. We should understand the cited particular conclusion from this principle that those statement of the Philosopher regarding things just by holding goods in trust should return the goods to nature as conclusions derived from general principles, the goods’ owners. And this is indeed true for the not as the general principles. And such conclusions most part, but it might in particular cases be are correct for the most part and are wanting in rather injurious, and so contrary to reason, to return the few cases. goods (e.g., if the owner should be seeking to Reply Obj. 3. As the power of reason in human attack one’s country). And the more the particular beings rules and commands other powers, so reason conclusion goes into particulars, the more exceptions needs to direct all the natural inclinations belong- there are (e.g., if one should declare that entrusted ing to other powers. And so it is universally correct goods should be returned to their owners with such for all persons to direct all their inclinations by and such safeguards or in such and such ways). reason. For the more particular conditions are added to the particular conclusion, the more ways there may FIFTH ARTICLE be exceptions, so that the conclusion about returning Can the Natural Law Vary? or not returning entrusted goods is erroneous. We thus proceed to the fifth inquiry. It seems that the Therefore, we should say that the natural law re- natural law can vary, for the following reasons: garding general first principles is the same for all Objection 1. A gloss on Sir. 17:9, “He [God] sup- persons both as to their rectitude and as to knowledge plied them with instruction and the law of life,” says: of them. And the natural law regarding particulars, “He wanted the [Old] Law to be written in order to which are, as it were, conclusions from the general correct the natural law.” But what is corrected is principles, is for the most part the same for all persons changed. Therefore, the natural law can vary. both as to its rectitude and as to knowledge of it. Obj. 2. The killing of innocent human beings as Nonetheless, it can be wanting in rather few cases well as adultery and theft are contrary to the natural both as to its rectitude and as to knowledge of it. As law. But God altered these precepts. For example, to rectitude, the natural law can be wanting because God on one occasion commanded Abraham to slay of particular obstacles, just as natures that come to his innocent son, as Gen. 22:2 relates. And God on be and pass away are wanting in rather few cases another occasion commanded the Jews to steal vessels because of obstacles. And also as to knowledge of the the Egyptians had lent them, as Ex. 12:35–36 relates. natural law, the law can be wanting because emotions And God on another occasion commanded Hosea to or evil habituation or evil natural disposition has per- take a fornicating wife, as Hos. 1:2 relates. Therefore, verted the reason of some. For example, the Germans the natural law can vary. of old did not consider robbery wicked, as Caesar’s Obj. 3. Isidore says in his Etymologies that “the Gallic Wars relates, although robbery is expressly con- common possession of all property and the same free- trary to the natural law. dom for all persons belong to the natural law.” But Reply Obj. 1. We should not understand the cited we perceive that human laws have altered these pre- statement to mean that all the matters included in scriptions. Therefore, it seems that the natural law the Law and the Gospel belong to the natural law, can vary. since the Law and the Gospel transmit to us many On the contrary, the Decretum says: “The natural things above nature. Rather, we should understand law originates with rational creatures. It does not vary the statement to mean that the Law and the Gospel over time and abides without change.” completely transmit to us the things that belong to I answer that we can understand the mutability of the natural law. And so Gratian, after saying that “the the natural law in two ways. We can understand it natural law is contained in the Law and the Gospel,” in one way by things being added to it. And then immediately adds by way of example: “And everyone nothing prevents the natural law changing, since both is thereby commanded to do unto others what one divine law and human laws add to natural law many wishes to be done to oneself.” things beneficial to human life. 474 AQUINAS We can understand the mutability of the natural we could say that it belongs to the natural law that law in a second way by way of substraction, namely, human beings are naked, since nature did not endow that things previously subject to the law cease to be them with clothes, which human skill created. And so. And then the natural law is altogether immutable it is in the latter way that we say that “the common as to its first principles. And as to its secondary pre- possession of all property and the same freedom for cepts, which we said are proper proximate conclu- all persons” belong to the natural law, namely, that sions, as it were, from the first principles, the natural the reason of human beings, not nature, introduced law is not so changed that what it prescribes is not private property and compulsory servitude. And so for the most part completely correct. But it can be the natural law in this respect varies only by way changed regarding particulars and in rather few cases, of addition. due to special causes that prevent observance of such precepts, as I have said before. SIXTH ARTICLE Reply Obj. 1. We say that written law has been Can the Natural Law Be Excised from the given to correct the natural law either because the Hearts of Human Beings? written law supplements what the natural law lacked, or because the natural law in the hearts of some We thus proceed to the sixth inquiry. It seems that regarding particulars had been corrupted insofar as the natural law can be excised from the hearts of they thought that things by nature evil were good. human beings, for the following reasons: And such corruption needed correction. Objection 1. A gloss on Rom. 2:14, “When the Reply Obj. 2. All human beings, without excep- Gentiles, who do not have the law,” etc., says: “The tion, both the innocent and the guilty, die when law of righteousness, which sin had wiped out, is natural death comes. And God’s power indeed inflicts inscribed on the inner human being renewed by such natural death on human beings because of origi- grace.” But the law of righteousness is the natural nal sin, as 1 Sam. 2:6 says: “The Lord causes death law. Therefore, the natural law can be wiped out. and life.” And so, at the command of God, death Obj. 2. The law of grace is more efficacious than can without any injustice be inflicted on any human the law of nature. But sin destroys the law of grace. being, whether guilty or innocent. Therefore, much more can the natural law be Likewise, adultery is sexual intercourse with an- wiped out. other man’s wife, whom the law handed down by Obj. 3. What law establishes is rendered just, as God has allotted to him. And so there is no adultery it were. But human beings have established many or fornication in having intercourse with any woman things contrary to the natural law. Therefore, the at the command of God. natural law can be excised from the hearts of hu- And the argument is the same regarding theft, man beings. which consists of taking another’s property. One does On the contrary, Augustine says in his Confessions: not take without the consent of the owner (i.e., steal) “Your law is inscribed on the hearts of human beings, anything that one takes at the command of God, who and indeed no wickedness wipes it out.” But the law is the owner of all property. inscribed on the hearts of human beings is the natural Nor is it only regarding human affairs that every- law. Therefore, the natural law cannot be wiped out. thing God commands is owed to him. Rather, regard- I answer that as I have said before, there belong ing things of nature, everything God does is also in to the natural law, indeed primarily, very general one respect natural, as I said in the First Part. precepts, precepts that everyone knows, and more Reply Obj. 3. We speak of things belonging to the particular, secondary precepts, which are like proxi- natural law in two ways. We speak of them belonging mate conclusions from first principles. Therefore, re- in one way because nature inclines us to them. For garding the general principles, the natural law in example, one should not cause injury to another. We general can in no way be excised from the hearts speak of them belonging in a second way because of human beings. But the natural law is wiped out nature did not introduce the contrary. For example, regarding particular actions insofar as desires or other Summa Theologica, Law, Question 95 475 emotions prevent reason from applying the general acts regard particular things, which are potentially principles to particular actions, as I have said before. infinite, no one except wise persons, who regard par- And the natural law can be excised from the hearts ticulars, can suffi ciently contemplate the things that of human be ings regarding the other, secondary belong to the direction of human acts. Therefore, it precepts, either because of wicked opin ions, just as would have been better that the decisions of wise per- errors in theoretical matters happen regard ing nec- sons direct human actions than that any est ablished essary conclusions, or because of evil customs or cor- law should. Therefore, there was no need to est ab- rupt habits. For example, some did not think robbery lish human laws. a sin, or even sins against nature to be sinful, as the On the contrary, Isidore says in his Etymologies: Apostle also says in Rom. 1:24–28. “Laws were est ablished so that fear of them curb Reply Obj. 1. Sin wipes out the natural law regard- human audacity, and that innocence be safe in the ing particulars but not in general, except perhaps re- midst of the wicked, and that the fear of punishment garding secondary precepts of the natural la w, in the restrain the ability of the wicked to inflict harm.” But way I mentioned. the human race most needs such things. Therefore, it Reply Obj. 2. Although grace is more effi cacious was necessary to establish human laws. than nature, nature is nonetheless more essential to I answer that, as is evident from what I have said human beings and so more abiding. before, human beings by nature have a capac ity for Reply Obj. 3. The argument of this objection is virtue, but they need to arrive at the very perfection of valid regarding the secondary precepts of the natural virtue by some training. Just so, we perceive that in- law, contrary to which some la wmakers have passed dustriousness helps them regard ing their necessities wicked statutes. (e.g., food and clothing). And nature gives them the sources to provide these necessities, namely , reason Question 95 and hands, not the full complement of the necessities that nature gives other animals, for whom nature has On Human Law sufficiently provided covering and food. But human beings are not readily self-sufficient in First Article regard to this training, since the perfection of virtue consists chiefly of human be ings’ restraint from ex- Was It Beneficial That Human Beings cessive pleasures, toward which they are most prone. Establish Laws? And this is especially true of youths, for whom train- We thus proceed to the first inquiry. It seems that it ing is more efficacious. And so human beings receive was not benefi cial that human beings establish laws, such training, whereby they arrive at virtue, from oth- for the following reasons: ers. And indeed regard ing youths prone to virtuous Objection 1. The purpose of every la w is to make acts by good natural d isposition or habituation (or, human beings good, as I have said before. But admo- rather, a gift from God), paternal train ing, which nitions induce human beings willingly to live rightly consists of admonitions, suffices. more than laws do coercively. Therefore, there was But some persons are wicked and prone to vices, no need to establish laws. and cannot be easily persuaded by words. Therefore, Obj. 2. The Philosopher says in theEthics: “Human force and fear were needed to restrain them from beings have recourse to judges as justice-in-the-flesh.” evil. Consequently, at least desisting from evil deeds, But justice-in-the-flesh is better than the inan imate they would both leave others in peace and be them- justice contained in laws. Therefore, it would have selves at length brought by such habituation to do been better to commit the execution of justice to the voluntarily what they hitherto did out of fear, and so decisions of judges than to est ablish laws to supple- become virtuous. But such train ing, which compels ment their decisions. by fear of punishment, is the training administered by Obj. 3. Every law directs human actions, as is evi- laws. And so it was necessary to establish laws in order dent from what I have said before. But since human that human beings live in peace and have virtue. For, 476 AQUINAS as the Philosopher says in the Politics: “As human be- obligations to which the natural law gives rise, it does ings, if perfect in virtue, are the best of animals, so are matter whether one effects justice in this or that way. they, if cut off from la w and justice, the worst of all Therefore, not all the things est ablished by human animals.” This is because human beings, unlike other laws are derived from the natural law. animals, have the tools of reason to satisfy their disor- Obj. 2. Positive law differs from natural la w, as dered desires and beastly rages. Isidore makes clear in his Etymologies and the Phi- Reply Obj. 1. Voluntary admonitions induce well losopher makes clear in the Ethics. But things de- disposed human beings to virtue better than compul- rived as conclusions from the general princ iples of sion does, but there are some who are not induced to the natural law belong to the natural la w, as I have virtue unless they be compelled. said before. Therefore, things proper to human la w Reply Obj. 2. The Philosopher says in the Rheto- are not derived from the natural law. ric: “It is better that law direct all things than that they Obj. 3. The natural la w is the same for all per- be left to the dec isions of judges.” And this is so for sons. For the Philosopher says in the Ethics that three reasons. First, indeed, it is easier to find the few “natural justice has the same force everywhere. ” wise persons sufficient to establish right laws than the Therefore, if human laws were to be derived from the many wise persons necessary to judge rightly about natural law, human laws would likewise be the same particular matters. Second, lawmakers consider over for all persons. But such a conclusion is evidently a long time what to impose by la w, but judges reach false. decisions about particular deeds as cases spont ane- Obj. 4. We can assign reasons for things derived ously arise. And human be ings can more easily per- from the natural law. But “one cannot assign reasons ceive what is right by considering many inst ances for all the st atutes rulers have decreed,” as the Jurist than they can by considering only one deed. Third, says. Therefore, some human la ws are not derived lawmakers decide in general and about future events, from the natural law. but presiding judges decide current cases, and love or On the contrary, Cicero says in his Rhetoric: “Fear hatred or covetousness affects such decisions. And so and reverence for the laws have prescribed things de- their decisions are perverted. rived from nature and approved by custom.” Therefore, since few embody the justice req uired I answer that Augustine says in his work On Free of a judge, and since that justice can be perverted, it Choice: “Unjust laws do not seem to be laws.” And so was necessary that law determine, whenever possible, laws have binding force insofar as they have justice. what judges should dec ide, and comm it very few And we say regard ing human affairs that things are matters to the decisions of human beings. just because they are right accord ing to the rule of Reply Obj. 3. “We need to commit to judges” cer- reason. But the primary rule of reason is the natural tain particular details, which laws cannot encompass, law, as is evident from what I have said before. And so as the Philosopher also says in the Rhetoric, such as, every human law has as much of the nature of law as “whether alleged deeds have or have not been done,” it is derived from the natural la w. And a human la w and the like. diverging in any way from the natural la w will be a perversion of law and no longer a law. Second Article But we should note that we can derive things from the natural law in two ways: in one way as con- Is Every Human Law Derived from the clusions from its fi rst principles; in a second way as Natural Law? specifications of cert ain general princ iples. Indeed, We thus proceed to the second inquiry. It seems that the first way is like the way in which we dra w con- not every human law is derived from the natural law, clusions from fi rst principles in theoretical sciences. for the following reasons: And the second way is like the way that craftsmen Objection 1. The Philosopher says in the Ethics in the course of exerc ising their skill adapt general that “it does not at all matter originally whether one forms to specific things. For example, a builder needs effects legal justice in this or that way.” But regarding to adapt the general form of a house to this or that Summa Theologica, Law, Question 95 477 shape of a house. Therefore, some things are derived accord with a country’s customs, suitable to time and from general principles of the natural law as conclu- place, necessary, useful, so clear that they cont ain sions. For example, one can derive the prohibition nothing obscure to cause deception, and decreed for against homicide from the general principle that one the common benefi t of all c itizens, not the private should do no evil to anyone. And some things are benefit of some.” It seems that he in this way inap- derived from general principles of the natural law as propriately describes the characteristics of positive specifications. For example, the natural la w ordains law, for the following reasons: that criminals should be punished, but that criminals Objection 1. Isidore previously had explained the be punished in this or that way is a spec ification of characteristics of la w in terms of three cond itions: the natural law. “Laws should be everything constituted by reason if Therefore, human laws are derived from the natu- befitting religion, suitable for training, and useful for ral law in both ways. Things derived from the natural the commonweal.” Therefore, he later unnecessarily law in the first way are not only contained in human added further conditions of law. laws as est ablished by those laws, but they also have Obj. 2. Justice is a virtue, as Cicero says in his part of their binding force from the natural la w. But work On Duties. Therefore, Isidore needlessly adds things derived from the natural law in the second way “just” after he mentioned “virtuous.” have all of their binding force from human law. Obj. 3. Isidore contrad istinguished written la ws Reply Obj. 1. The Philosopher is speaking about from customs. Therefore, he ought not to have pos- the things laws decreed by determining or specifying ited in the defi nition of law that laws be “in accord one of the precepts of the natural law. with a country’s customs.” Reply Obj. 2. The argument of this objection is Obj. 4. We call things necessary in two ways. valid regarding things derived from the natural law as Things that cannot be otherwise, are absolutely nec- conclusions. essary, and such necessary things are not subject to Reply Obj. 3. The general principles of the natu- human judgment. And so such necessity does not be- ral law cannot be applied to all peoples in the same long to human la w. Other things are necessary for way because of the great variety of human affairs. ends, and such necessity is the same as usefulness. And so there are d ifferent positive laws for different Therefore, Isidore needlessly posits both “necessary” peoples. and “useful” as characteristics of law. Reply Obj. 4. We should underst and the J urist’s On the contrary, there stands the authority of Isidore statement to regard things decreed by rulers about himself. particular specifications of the natural la w. And the I answer that we need to determine the form of any judgments of experienced and prudent persons are means in relation to the end desired. F or example, indeed related to such specifications as certain prin- the form of a saw is such as to be suit able for cutting ciples underlying their judgments, namely, inasmuch wood, as the Physics makes clear. Likewise, every- as they immediately perceive what is the most fi tting thing ruled and measured needs to have a form ap- particular specification. And so the Philosopher says portioned to its rule or measure. And human law has in the Ethics that “we should” in such matters “at- both, since it is both something ordained for an end tend to the intuitive st atements and opinions of the and a rule or measure ruled or measured by a higher experienced and the mature or prudent no less than measure. And the higher measure is indeed of two to their arguments.” kinds, namely, the divine law and the natural law, as is evident from what I have said before. But the end Third Article of human law is the benefi t of human beings, as the Jurist also says. And so indeed Isidore fi rst posited Does Isidore Appropriately Describe the three things as conditions of human law, namely, that Characteristics of Positive Law? human law benefit religion (i.e., as human la w is We thus proceed to the third inquiry. Isidore says: properly related to the divine law), that human law “Laws should be virtuous, just, possible by nature, in be suitable for training (i.e., as human law is properly 478 AQUINAS related to the natural law), that human human law be contained in the natural la w rather than positive useful for the commonweal (i.e., as human la w is human law. properly related to human usefulness). Obj. 2. Things that have the same bind ing force And all the other conditions that he later mentions seem to differ only materially, not formally. But “stat- are traceable to these three things. F or what he calls utes, plebiscites, decrees of the senate,” and the other virtuous is a reference to what befits religion. And by like things Isidore describes all have the same bind- adding that human laws be “just, possible by nature, ing force. Therefore, they seem to differ only mate- in accord with a country’ s customs, suit able to the rially. But artisans should pay no attention to such place and time,” he indicates that the laws should be differences, since there can be an endless number of suitable for train ing. For we indeed fi rst consider them. Therefore, Isidore inappropriately introduces human training in relation to the ord ination of rea- such divisions. son, which ordination is implied in what he calls just. Obj. 3. As there are rulers and priests and soldiers Second, we consider human train ing in relation to in political communities, so human beings also have the capacity of human agents. F or training ought to other public duties. Therefore, as Isidore posits “mili- be suitable to each according to the capacity of each, tary law” and “public law” (which govern priests and including natural capacity. (For example, one should magistrates), so he should also posit other la ws per- not impose the same train ing on children that one taining to other public duties. imposes on adults.) And training ought to be suitable Obj. 4. We should ignore accidental things. But it according to human customs, since human beings do is accidental to laws whether they are framed by this not live in soc iety by themselves, not man ifesting or that human being. Therefore, Isidore inappropri- their behavior to others. Third, in relation to requisite ately posits a d ivision of laws by the names of the ir circumstances, he says: “suit able to the place and framers, namely, that one is called the Cornelian law, time.” And the add itional words, “necessary,” “use- another the Falcidian law, and so forth. ful,” and so forth, refer to what fac ilitates the com- On the contrary, the authority of Isidore suffices. monweal. For example, necessity refers to removing I answer that we can intrinsically distinguish each evils, usefulness to acq uiring benefits, and clarifi - thing by what belongs to its nature. For example, the cation to preventing harm that could arise from the nature of animals includes a soul that is rational or laws themselves. nonrational. And so we properly and intrinsically dis- And he indicates that human laws are ordained for tinguish animals by whether they are rational or irra- the common good, as I have previously affi rmed, in tional, and not by whether they are black or white, the last part of the definition. which are characteristics altogether outside the nature Reply Objs. 1–4. The answer makes clear the re- of animals. plies to the objections. And many characteristics belong to the nature of human laws, and we can properly and intrinsically Fourth Article distinguish human laws by any of those things. F or example, it first of all belongs to the nature of human Does Isidore Appropriately Designate laws that they be derived from the natural la w, as is Kinds of Human Law? evident from what I have said before. And we in this We thus proceed to the fourth inquiry. It seems that respect divide positive laws into the common la w of Isidore does not appropriately designate kinds of peoples and the la ws of particular commonwealths human law, for the following reasons: by the two ways in which things may be derived from Objection 1. Isidore includes in human la w “the the natural law, as I have said before. F or precepts common law of peoples,” which he so names, as he derived from the natural la w as conclusions from its says, because “almost every people possesses it.” But general principles belong to the common law of peo- “natural law is common to all peoples, ” as he him- ples (e.g., just buying and selling, and the like, with- self says. Therefore, the common la w of peoples is out which human be ings cannot live soc iably with Summa Theologica, Law, Question 96 479 one another). And living sociably with others belongs nate by the ir authors, by the la ws’ different subject to the natural law, since human beings are by nature matter. For example, we d istinguish the Julian Law social animals, as the Politics proves. But precepts on adultery, the Cornelian Law on assassination, and derived from the natural la w by way of particular the like, because of their subject matter, not because specifications belong to the la ws of particular com- of their authors. monwealths, whereby each commonwealth specifies Reply Obj. 1. The common la w of peoples is in- things suitable for itself. deed natural for human beings in one respect, insofar Second, it belongs to the nature of human la ws as it is rational, since it is derived from the natural law that they be ordained for the common good of a po- as conclusions not very remote from general princ i- litical community. And we can in this respect d istin- ples of the natural la w. And so human be ings easily guish human laws by the d ifferent kinds of persons agree about such matters. But we distinguish the com- who perform particular t asks for the common good mon law of peoples from the natural la w, especially (e.g., priests, who pray to God for the people; rulers, from what is common to all animals. who govern the people; sold iers, who fi ght for the Reply Objs. 2–4. The replies to these objections is safety of the people). And so special laws are adapted evident from what I have said. for such persons. Third, it belongs to the nature of human laws that Question 96 they be established by those who govern the political community, as I have said before. And we in this re- spect distinguish human laws by the d ifferent forms On the Power of Human Laws of governing political communities. And as the Phi- losopher says in the Politics, one of these forms is First Article monarchy (i.e., rule by one person). And we under- Should Human Laws Be Framed in stand the laws of monarchical regimes as royal de- Particular Rather Than General Terms? crees. And aristocracy (i.e., rule by the best persons or aristocrats) is another form of government. And we We thus proceed to the first inquiry. It seems that understand the laws of aristocratic regimes as the au- human laws should be framed in particular rather thoritative legal opinions of the wise, and also as the than general terms, for the following reasons: decrees of the senate. And oligarchy (i.e., rule by a Objection 1. The Philosopher says in the Ethics few rich and po werful persons) is another form of that “things of the legal order consist of everything government. And we underst and the laws of oligar- laws decree about individual matters, and likewise of chical regimes as magisterial la w, also called la w by judicial decisions,” which also concern particular dignitaries. And another form of government is by the matters, since judges hand down decisions on partic- people, which form we call democracy. And we un- ular cases. Therefore, laws are framed both in general derstand the laws of democratic regimes as la ws by and in particular terms. the people. (Tyranny is another form of government, Obj. 2. Laws direct human actions, as I have said an altogether corrupt form, and so we do not under- before. But human actions consist of particular stand the la ws of tyrann ical regimes as any la w.) things. Therefore, laws should be framed in particu- There is also a form of government that is a m ixture lar rather than general terms. of the good forms, and this m ixed form of govern- Obj. 3. Laws are the rules and measures of human ment is the best. And we understand the laws of such actions, as I have said before. But measures should regimes as law “prescribed by elders and the people,” be most certain, as the Metaphysics says. Therefore, as Isidore says. since nothing about human actions can be so univer- Fourth, it belongs to the nature of human la ws sally certain as not to be wanting in particular cases, that they direct human actions. And we in this re- it seems that la ws need to be framed in particular spect distinguish laws, which we sometimes desig- rather than general terms. 480 AQUINAS On the contrary, the Jurist says: “Laws need to be vidual commands to d irect individual actions, but framed to suit things that more freq uently happen, law is a general command, as I have said. and laws are not framed to suit things that can hap- Reply Obj. 3. “One should not look for the same pen once in a while.” certainty in all kinds of things, ” as the Ethics says. I answer that everything for an end needs to be pro- And so in the case of contingent things like natural portioned to the end. But the end of la w is the com- events and human affairs, there is sufficient certainty mon good, since “laws should be framed for the com- if things are true for the most part, even though they mon benefit of citizens, not for any private benefi t,” sometimes fail to happen in relatively few cases. as Isidore says in his Etymologies. And so human laws need to be proportioned to the common good. But Second Article the common good consists of many things. And so laws Does It Belong to Human Laws to need to regard many things, both persons, matters, and Prohibit All Vices? times. For the political community consists of many persons, and its good is procured by many actions. We thus proceed to the second inquiry. It seems that it Nor is it instituted to endure only for a short time but belongs to human la ws to prohibit all vices, for the to last for all time through successive generations of following reasons: citizens, as Augustine says in The City of God. Objection 1. Isidore says in his Etymologies that Reply Obj. 1. The Philosopher in the Ethics posits “laws have been est ablished in order to curb human three parts of legal justice (i.e., positive la w). For audacity out of fear of them. ” But human audac ity there are certain prescriptions framed only in general would not be suffi ciently curbed unless laws were to terms, and these are general laws. And regarding such prohibit everything evil. Therefore, human laws ought laws, he says that “legal justice indeed does not origi- to prohibit everything evil. nally differentiate in particulars but does once est ab- Obj. 2. The aim of lawmakers is to make c itizens lished.” For example, captives are ransomed at a fixed virtuous. But citizens can be virtuous only if they are price. And there are some laws that are general in one curbed of all vices. Therefore, it belongs to human respect and particular in another. And we call such law to curb all vices. laws privileges, that is, private laws, since they regard Obj. 3. Human law is derived from natural law, as particular persons, and yet the po wer of these la ws I have said before. But all sins are contrary to the extends to many matters. And it is regard ing these natural law. Therefore, human law ought to prohibit that the Philosopher adds: “And, further, everything all vices. laws decree in particular cases.” On the contrary, Augustine says in his work On And we call some things legal because general Free Choice: “It seems to me that laws written for the laws are applied to particular cases, not because the people’s governance rightly perm it such things, and applications are laws. For example, judges hand down that God’s providence pun ishes them.” But God’ s decisions that we consider legally bind ing. And it is providence only punishes sins. Therefore, human laws, regarding such that the Philosopher adds: “And judi- by not prohibiting some sins, rightly permit them. cial decisions.” I answer that laws are est ablished as the rules or Reply Obj. 2. Something directive needs to direct measures of human actions, as I have already said. several things, and so the Philosopher says in the But measures should be homogeneous with what Metaphysics that all the things belonging to a gen us they measure, as the Metaphysics says, since different are measured by the one of them that primarily be- kinds of things are measured by d ifferent kinds of longs to the gen us. For if there were to be as many measures. And so la ws need also to be imposed on rules or measures as things measured or ruled, a rule human beings according to the ir condition, since or measure, which is that one thing enable many laws ought to be “possible regarding both nature and things to be kno wn, would cease to be of any use. a country’s customs,” as Isidore says. And the po wer And so a la w would have no usefulness if it were to or ability to act results from internal habituation cover only a single action. For wise persons give indi- or disposition, since the virtuous and those without Summa Theologica, Law, Question 96 481 virtuous habits do not have the same po wer to act. Third Article Just so, children and adults do not have the same Do Human Laws Command Every power to act, and so the la w is not the same for chil- Virtuous Action? dren and adults. For example, many things are per- mitted children that the la w punishes in adults, or We thus proceed to the third inquiry. It seems that even that public opin ion censures. And likewise, human laws do not command every virtuous action, many things are tolerated in persons of imperfect vir- for the following reasons: tue that would not be tolerated in virtuous persons. Objection 1. Vicious actions are the contrary of And human law is est ablished for the collectivity of virtuous actions. But human laws do not prohibit all human beings, most of whom have imperfect virtue. vices, as I have said. Therefore, human la ws also do And so human la w does not prohibit every kind of not command every virtuous action. vice, from which the virtuous abstain. Rather, human Obj. 2. Virtuous actions come from virtue. But law prohibits only the more serious kinds of vice, virtue is the aim of la ws, and so what comes from from which most persons can abstain, and especially virtue cannot fall within legal precepts. Therefore, those vices that infl ict harm on others, without the human laws do not command every virtuous action. prohibition of which human soc iety could not be Obj. 3. Laws are ordained for the common good, preserved. For example, human laws prohibit mur- as I have said. But some virtuous actions are ordained ders, thefts, and the like. for private, not the common, good. Therefore, la ws Reply Obj. 1. Audacity seems to belong to att acks do not command every virtuous action. on others. And so audacity belongs chiefly to the sins On the contrary, the Philosopher says in the Ethics: that inflict injury on neighbors, and human law pro- “Laws command courageous and temperate and gen- hibits such sins, as I have said. tle behavior, and likewise regarding other virtues and Reply Obj. 2. Human laws aim to induce human vices, commanding the former and forbidd ing the beings to virtue little by little, not all at once. And so latter.” the laws do not immediately impose on the many im- I answer that we distinguish specific virtues by perfect citizens what already belongs to virtuous citi- their objects, as is evident from what I have said be- zens, namely, that c itizens abstain from everything fore. But we can relate all the objects of virtues either evil. Otherwise, the imperfect c itizens, unable to to the private good of a person or to the common endure those commands, would erupt into worse evil good of the people. F or example, one can perform things. Just so, Prov. 30:33 says: “Those who blo w courageous acts either to preserve the political com- their nose too strongly , emit blood.” And Mt. 9:17 munity or to uphold the rights of one’ s friends, and says: “If one should put new wine, ” that is, the pre- similarly with other virtuous acts. And la ws are or- cepts of a perfect life, “into old wineskins, ” that is, dained for the common good, as I have said. And imperfect human beings, “the wineskins burst, and so there are no virtues regard ing whose actions la ws the wine is spilled,” that is, the precepts are despised, could not command. But la ws do not command re- and human beings burst into worse evil things out of garding every action of every virtue. Rather, they only contempt. command things that can be ordained for the com- Reply Obj. 3. The natural law is our participation mon good, whether immediately, as when things are in the eternal la w, but human la w falls short of the done directly for that good, or med iately, as when eternal law. For Augustine says in his work On Free lawmakers ordain things belonging to good train ing, Choice: “The laws framed for the governance of which trains citizens to preserve the common good political communities permit and leave unpunished of justice and peace. many things that God’ s providence pun ishes. Nor, Reply Obj. 1. Human laws do not by strict com- indeed, should we critic ize what the la ws do do be- mand prohibit every vic ious action, just as they do cause of the fact that they do not do everything.” And not command every virtuous action. But human laws so also human la ws cannot prohibit everything that prohibit some acts of particular vices, just as they the natural law prohibits. command some acts of particular virtues. 482 AQUINAS Reply Obj. 2. We call actions virtuous in two ways. I answer that laws established by human beings are We call them virtuous in one way because persons either just or unjust. If just, they indeed have obliga- perform virtuous deeds. F or example, just actions tory force in the court of conscience from the eternal consist of doing just things, brave actions consist of law, from which they are derived. J ust so, Prov. 8:15 doing brave things. And human laws command virtu- says: “Kings rule through me, and la wmakers decree ous acts in this way. We call actions virtuous in a sec- justice.” And we call la ws just from three perspec- ond way because persons per

Use Quizgecko on...
Browser
Browser