Unit 2 Summary PDF

Loading...
Loading...
Loading...
Loading...
Loading...
Loading...
Loading...

Document Details

CharmingGraph1619

Uploaded by CharmingGraph1619

UP Diliman

Tags

philosophy epistemology logic knowledge claims

Summary

This document is about the analysis of statements, knowledge claims, and their associated principles, including identity, non-contradiction, and excluded middle. The distinction between sentences and statements is highlighted, and examples of declarative, interrogative, imperative, and exclamatory sentences are presented.

Full Transcript

Module 1 - Analysis of Statements This module explores the distinction between sentences and statements, the nature of knowledge claims, and the principles of identity, non-contradiction, and excluded middle. Here’s a breakdown of the key objectives: 1. Dist...

Module 1 - Analysis of Statements This module explores the distinction between sentences and statements, the nature of knowledge claims, and the principles of identity, non-contradiction, and excluded middle. Here’s a breakdown of the key objectives: 1. Distinction Between Sentences and Statements: Sentences are linguistic expressions that can take various forms, such as interrogative, imperative, exclamatory, and declarative. These types do not necessarily convey truth or falsehood. Interrogative Sentences: These sentences are used to ask questions. No truth values. Imperative Sentences: Imperative sentences are used to give commands or instructions. No truth values. Exclamatory Sentences: These sentences express strong feelings such as surprise, joy, or frustration. No truth values. Expletive Sentences: Expletive sentences express wishes, desires, or hopes. No truth values. Declarative Sentences: Declarative sentences are used to assert or deny something about the world, and they are the ones that can be true or false. When you make a knowledge claim, you use declarative sentences, which are the subject of logical and philosophical analysis because they can be evaluated for their truth value. Statements (or propositions), on the other hand, are the bearers of truth-values. A declarative sentence, when used to assert something about the world, expresses a statement. Statements are evaluated as true or false, depending on their alignment with reality. Example: “The cat is on the mat” is a statement that can be true if the cat is actually on the mat, or false if it is not. Importantly, philosophers distinguish between the material sentence (made up of words) and the immaterial statement (a construct used for philosophical analysis). 2. Nature of Knowledge Claims: A knowledge claim is made when a declarative sentence is used to assert or deny something about the world. This transforms a sentence into a statement or proposition. The truth-value of a knowledge claim is determined by external realities (e.g., whether or not the situation described actually occurs). Truth and Falsehood: The validity of a knowledge claim depends on whether the state of a airs it describes corresponds with the actual world. 3. Principles of Identity, Non-Contradiction, and Excluded Middle: Principle of Identity: If a statement is true, it remains true over time, assuming that the relevant terms and conditions remain unchanged. This principle ensures that truth-values are stable and consistent. Example: “All bachelors are unmarried males” remains true inde nitely unless the de nition of “bachelor” changes. Principle of Non-Contradiction: A statement cannot be both true and false at the same time and in the same context. This principle prevents contradictory assertions within logical analysis. Example: “The blackboard is green” and “The blackboard is not green” cannot both be true simultaneously. ff fi fi Principle of Excluded Middle: A statement is either true or false, with no third option. This is a fundamental principle of two-valued deductive logic. Statements cannot be “probably” true in this system. Example: “The blackboard is green” is either true or false; there is no middle ground like “possibly green.” 4. Contradictory vs. Inconsistent Statements: Contradictory statements: One statement is true, and its denial must be false. If one is true, the other is false, and vice versa. Example: “The blackboard is green” contradicts “The blackboard is not green.” Inconsistent statements: These can both be false but cannot both be true. They involve mutually exclusive claims that are inconsistent with each other but do not necessarily contradict. Example: “The blackboard is green” is inconsistent with “The blackboard is yellow.” Both could be false if the blackboard is black, but both cannot be true at the same time. Conclusion: The module emphasizes the philosophical and logical importance of distinguishing between sentences and statements, understanding knowledge claims, and applying the principles of identity, non-contradiction, and excluded middle. These concepts are foundational to logical reasoning and epistemological inquiry, allowing one to analyze the truth-values of statements and the consistency of arguments e ectively. Module 2 - Rationalism and Empiricism 1. Three Central Issues in Epistemology: The foundation of epistemology is built around three core questions: What is the source of knowledge? What can be known? How do we validate knowledge claims? Every theory of knowledge, from ancient times to modern philosophy, must provide answers to these issues. They form the basis for comparing rationalism and empiricism, as these two traditions respond di erently to these questions. 2. Rationalism: Rationalism, as represented by philosophers like René Descartes, Baruch Spinoza, and Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, posits that reason is the sole source of knowledge. Rationalists argue that: Reason alone can provide certainty in knowledge, primarily through the formal sciences (like logic, mathematics, and geometry). Sensory perception is deemed unreliable because the senses can often deceive us, as evidenced by perceptual illusions. Examples include how a distant tower looks smaller or how an oar submerged in water appears bent. They adhere to the coherence theory of truth, which holds that a belief is true if it is logically consistent with other beliefs in a system. ff ff Rationalists focus on a priori knowledge, which refers to knowledge that is independent of experience and is derived purely from reason. 3. Empiricism: Empiricists, including John Locke, George Berkeley, and David Hume, argue that while reason is a source of knowledge, it is experience, particularly through the ve senses, that plays the dominant role in acquiring knowledge about the physical world. Empiricists maintain that knowledge must come from impressions (sensory experiences) and the ideas that arise from those impressions. Empirical knowledge is based on a posteriori reasoning, meaning it is derived from experience. They argue that matters of fact (knowledge about the physical world) can only be ascertained through sensory data. Hume further distinguishes between two types of perceptions: impressions (vivid sensory experiences) and ideas (faint images or re ections of these impressions). Empiricists adopt the correspondence theory of truth, where a statement is true if it corresponds to the facts of the real world. Importantly, empiricists disagree with rationalists’ claim that reason alone can provide knowledge of the physical world. They argue that reason can only guarantee formal knowledge (like mathematics and logic), which does not have any empirical content. 4. Comparison of Rationalism and Empiricism: Source of Knowledge: Rationalists believe knowledge comes solely from reason, while empiricists argue that knowledge comes from both reason and sensory experience. Types of Knowledge: Rationalists focus on formal knowledge (analytic truths, as in logic and mathematics), while empiricists emphasize empirical knowledge (synthetic truths, as in knowledge of the physical world). Theory of Truth: Rationalists support the coherence theory of truth, and empiricists accept both coherence and correspondence theories. Perceptual Reliability: Rationalists reject the reliability of the senses due to perceptual illusions, whereas empiricists acknowledge the limitations of sensory data but still argue it is the best tool we have to understand the external world. 5. Two Types of Knowledge Claims: The distinction between two types of knowledge claims originates from the work of both rationalist and empiricist philosophers: Truths of Reason by Leibniz (Relations of Ideas by Hume): These are analytic statements, true by virtue of their meaning. They are necessarily true and cannot be denied without contradiction. Examples include mathematical truths (e.g., 3 + 5 = 8). Truths of Fact by Leibniz (Matters of Fact by Hume): These are synthetic statements based on sensory experience, and their truth can only be con rmed through empirical veri cation. Denying these statements is logically possible and does not lead to contradiction (e.g., “The sun will rise tomorrow”). Immanuel Kant later synthesized rationalism and empiricism, suggesting that while reason provides the structure of knowledge, experience lls it with content. fi fl fi fi fi 6. Dogma of Knowledge Distinction: The 20th-century logical positivists perpetuated the distinction between two types of knowledge claims: formal and empirical. This distinction remains in uential today, especially in the classi cation of sciences into formal (e.g., mathematics, logic) and empirical sciences (e.g., physics, biology). The module uses the terms analytic and empirical statements to represent these two types of knowledge claims. Furthermore, Hume’s contribution remains critical: the denial of analytic statements (truths of reason) leads to contradiction, while the denial of empirical statements (truths of fact) does not. This distinction plays a crucial role in philosophical analysis. 7. Conclusion: This module sets the stage for a deeper exploration of epistemology, providing a foundational understanding of the three central issues and how they are addressed by rationalism and empiricism. Through the lens of these two traditions, learners will also understand the di erence between truth of reason and truth of fact, as well as the underlying theories of truth. This prepares students for further analysis of the coherence and correspondence theories of truth, as well as the role of analytic and empirical arguments in philosophical discourse. Module 3 - Types of Knowledge Claims 1. Signi cance of the Epistemology of Logical Positivism Logical positivism, originating from philosophers like Moritz Schlick in the 1930s, builds upon David Hume’s theory that knowledge arises from two sources: reason and sense perception. Hume’s distinction forms the basis for the logical positivist framework, classifying all knowledge into formal knowledge (derived from reason, e.g., mathematics, logic) and empirical knowledge (derived from the senses, e.g., natural and social sciences). Logical positivism asserts that all meaningful knowledge claims must be either analytic (based on reason) or empirical (based on sense perception), a view that continues to in uence how sciences are classi ed today, despite the decline of logical positivism in modern philosophy. 2. Comparison between Empirical and Analytic Claims Empirical claims are those that can be veri ed through sensory experience, often involving descriptions of the world. For example, “The sun will rise tomorrow” or “The weather is warm” are empirical claims, as their truth can be observed through the senses. Analytic claims, in contrast, are statements that are true by de nition and involve logical or formal knowledge. For instance, “All bachelors are unmarried males” or “Triangles have three sides” are analytic because their truth is contained within the de nition of the terms used. Denying such statements would lead to contradictions. Key Distinction: The test for an empirical statement is veri cation through observation (correspondence theory), while analytic statements are tested for logical coherence (coherence theory). fl ff fi fi fi fi fi fi fl fi 3. Relation between Source of Knowledge and Knowledge Claims Reason produces formal/analytic knowledge, where the truth of a statement is determined by logical relationships within a system (e.g., mathematics, logic). This type of knowledge is self-contained and independent of external reality. Sense perception produces empirical knowledge, where the truth is dependent on observing the external world (e.g., scienti c observations). The truth of empirical statements is established by verifying their correspondence to facts in the real world. Veri cation methods depend on the nature of the knowledge claim: coherence theory applies to formal knowledge, while correspondence theory applies to empirical knowledge. 4. Status of Evaluative Claims Evaluative claims express judgments of value, morality, or aesthetics (e.g., “Stealing is wrong,” “The sunset is beautiful”). According to Hume, these claims arise from passions and emotions, not reason or sense perception. While logical positivists may dismiss evaluative claims as meaningless because they are neither empirical nor analytic, Hume argues that these judgments are grounded in human emotional experience and are therefore valid forms of knowledge. Evaluative claims can be prescriptive (giving commands) or proscreptive (prohibitions), and they depend on public approval or consensus for justi cation rather than logical veri cation. 5. Application of Correspondence and Coherence Theories of Truth Correspondence theory is used to verify empirical claims by checking if they correspond to observable facts in the external world. For example, “The room is cold” can be tested through sensory experience. Coherence theory, on the other hand, is applied to analytic claims, where truth is determined by logical consistency within a system. For instance, “2 + 2 = 4” is true because it coheres with the rules of arithmetic. For evaluative claims, neither correspondence nor coherence theories directly apply. Instead, the inter-subjective agreement or public consensus of a concerned group often determines their validity. Objectives: 1. Signi cance of Logical Positivism: Logical positivism’s epistemological framework in uences the division of knowledge into formal (reason-based) and empirical (sense- based) types, although it has faced challenges, particularly regarding evaluative claims. 2. Comparison of Empirical and Analytic Claims: Empirical claims rely on observation and are veri ed through correspondence theory, while analytic claims are grounded in de nitions and logic, veri ed through coherence theory. 3. Relation between Source of Knowledge and Knowledge Claims: The two sources of knowledge—reason and sense perception—give rise to di erent types of claims, with distinct veri cation methods based on the source. 4. Status of Evaluative Claims: Evaluative claims, based on emotions and passions, are judged not by logical or empirical standards but by consensus or societal approval, distinguishing them from analytic and empirical claims. 5. Application of Correspondence and Coherence Theories: Theories of truth are applied based on the type of claim: coherence theory for formal, analytic claims, and fl fi fi fi fi fi fi fi fi ff fi correspondence theory for empirical claims. Evaluative claims are justi ed through consensus. Module 4 - Theories of Truth 1. Comparison and Contrast: Coherence and Correspondence Theory of Truth Coherence Theory and Correspondence Theory are two prominent theories in philosophy used to de ne truth. Coherence Theory of Truth emphasizes that a statement is true if it coheres or aligns with a system of related propositions. In this theory, coherence is de ned relationally, meaning it depends on the relationship between di erent elements, such as knowledge claims and formal systems like logic, mathematics, or empirical systems. For example, statements like “5 + 7 = 12” cohere within arithmetic, and logical tautologies like “If your statement is true, then it is true” cohere within symbolic logic. The key to coherence theory is the internal consistency of knowledge claims within these systems. Correspondence Theory of Truth, on the other hand, asserts that truth depends on the correspondence between knowledge claims and reality. For a statement to be true, it must correspond to actual facts or states of a airs in the real world. For example, the statement “The cat is on the mat” is true only if, in reality, a cat is physically on a mat. This theory is more controversial because it involves verifying claims by comparing them to external realities, unlike the internal focus of coherence theory. Key Di erences: Coherence Theory focuses on internal consistency within a system of knowledge, while Correspondence Theory relies on external veri cation with reality. Coherence Theory often applies to abstract systems (e.g., logic, mathematics), while Correspondence Theory is typically used to verify empirical claims about the world. 2. Di erent Versions of Correspondence Theory There are several versions of the Correspondence Theory, which deal with the relationship between knowledge claims and reality in di erent ways. Realist Version: This version focuses on direct observation and evidence from reality. If a claim refers to something happening in the present (e.g., “The girl is wearing a red dress”), it corresponds to truth by direct observation. For predictions (e.g., “The sun will rise tomorrow”), correspondence relies on past observations of regular patterns. Historical claims require veri cation through documents or eyewitness accounts. Empirical Generalizations: In this version, general claims (e.g., “Most professors are quali ed to teach”) correspond to truth by drawing on representative samples or populations. The realist version is widely used because it applies not only to empirical claims but also to evaluative claims, such as moral judgments. 3. Application of Veri cation by Inter-Subjective Consensus Inter-subjective consensus is used as a method of verifying evaluative claims under the Correspondence Theory. This method involves gathering agreement from a group or society on ff fi ff fi fi fi ff ff ff fi fi fi particular values or norms. For instance, the claim “Stealing is wrong” can be veri ed if there is a strong consensus among people sharing the same moral or social framework. If a group agrees that plagiarism is wrong, this consensus can be used to verify the truth of the evaluative claim “Plagiarism is wrong.” Moral and Legal Claims: Evaluative judgments, such as moral rule or principle (e.g., “Do not plagiarize”), rely on inter-subjective consensus. The stronger the consensus among the public, the more veri able the claim becomes. Veri cation here depends on the alignment of personal judgments with widely accepted moral systems. There is a strong intersubjective consensus that if you accept the evaluative claim Plagiarism is wrong then you must also accept the proscription Do not plagiarize is right, otherwise you will be guilty of dissonance. 4. Deontological and Teleological Justi cations Deontological Justi cations: In this approach, an act or policy is justi ed based on its inherent nature, regardless of the consequences. For example, if a policy like “Total logging ban should be implemented” is considered good in itself, it is justi ed deontologically. The moral value of the act is intrinsic, and no further justi cation is required from its outcomes. Teleological Justi cations: This justi cation depends on the consequences of an act or policy. In the teleological approach, something is considered good if it leads to positive outcomes. For instance, “Gambling in casinos is legalized” may be justi ed teleologically if it bene ts the economy. The morality of the act is determined by its results rather than the act itself. Combination of Both: The strongest form of justi cation is when an act or policy is good both in itself (deontologically) and produces bene cial outcomes (teleologically), such as when a policy is deemed just and has no harmful consequences. Module 5 - Your Obligation as a Critical Thinker 1. Apply Your Obligation as a Critical Thinker: The fundamental obligation as a critical thinker is to never accept any statement or belief without adequate evidence. This is rooted in healthy skepticism, which requires either rejecting beliefs without evidence or suspending judgment until su cient evidence is provided. This epistemic commitment demands careful evaluation of all claims before believing in them, even those made by authoritative gures. Over time, adhering to this principle fosters critical and independent thinking, reducing the acceptance of rumors, gossip, or unprovable claims. 2. Distinguish the Realm of the Known, Knowable, and Unknowable: The distinction between the known, knowable, and unknowable is essential for critical thinking. The known includes established facts and knowledge supported by evidence (e.g., the existence of DNA, black holes). The knowable involves claims that are currently being explored or could become known in the future, like cloning humans or understanding the origins of life. This realm lies between the known and unknowable and requires ongoing scienti c or empirical inquiry. The unknowable comprises claims that cannot, in principle, be supported by evidence, such as beliefs in heaven, hell, or reincarnation. These claims are beyond the scope of empirical investigation and thus remain unknowable. fi fi fi fi fi fi fi fi fi fi fi fi ffi fi fi fi fi 3. Distinguish the Realm of the Provable and Unprovable: Critical thinkers must discern between provable and unprovable claims. Provable claims fall within the realms of the known and the knowable, where evidence can either be produced or hypothetically produced. Unprovable claims reside in the realm of the unknowable, where no evidence can support the claims, making them unveri able. As a result, critical thinkers are advised to reject these claims unless they are considered evaluative (e.g., based on consensus or language games in speci c contexts), in which case they are subjective and not empirically provable. The overarching goal for a critical thinker is to classify claims appropriately: accept only those in the realm of the known, suspend judgment on those in the realm of the knowable, and reject those in the realm of the unknowable. fi fi

Use Quizgecko on...
Browser
Browser