Religion as a Cultural System PDF
Document Details
Clifford Geertz
Tags
Summary
This paper, by Clifford Geertz, discusses the anthropological study of religion, arguing that it hasn't made significant theoretical advances since World War II. It emphasizes the need for a broader conceptual framework that includes perspectives from other disciplines like philosophy and history, to advance the anthropological understanding of religion. The paper offers a definition of religion as a system of symbols that creates moods, motivations, and conceptions of existence.
Full Transcript
Geertz, Clifford Religion as a cultural system Readers are reminded that copyright subsists in this extract and the work from which it was taken. Except as provided for by the terms of a rightsholder's licence or copyright law, no further copying, storage or distribution is permitted without the c...
Geertz, Clifford Religion as a cultural system Readers are reminded that copyright subsists in this extract and the work from which it was taken. Except as provided for by the terms of a rightsholder's licence or copyright law, no further copying, storage or distribution is permitted without the consent of the copyright holder.The author (or authors) of the Literary Work or Works contained within the Licensed Material is or are the author(s) and may have moral rights in the work. The Licensee shall not cause or permit the distortion, mutilation or other modification of, or other derogatory treatment of, the work which would be prejudicial to the honour or reputation of the author. Geertz, Clifford, Religion as a cultural system. In: The interpretation of cultures: selected essays, Geertz, Clifford, pp.87-125. Fontana Press, 1993. This is a digital version of copyright material made under licence from the rightsholder, and its accuracy cannot be guaranteed. Please refer to the original published edition. Licenced for use at University of Oxford for the The Christian Doctrine of Creation course(s) running during the period 06/10/2003 to 05/10/2004. ISN: 0006862608 Permission reference: H0006862608(87-125)39433 Chapter 4/Religion As a Cultural System Any attempt to speak without speaking any particular language is not more hopeless than the attempt to have a religion that shall be no religion in particular.... Thus every living and healthy religion has a marked idiosyncrasy. Its power consists in its special and surprising message and in the bias which that reve- lation gives to life. The vistas it opens and the mysteries it propounds are another world to live in; and another world to live in—whether we expect ever to pass wholly over into it or no—is what we mean by having a reli- gion. SANTAYANA, Reason in Religion I Two characteristics of anthropological work on religion accomplished since the second world war strike me as curious when such work is placed against that carried out just before and just after the first. One is that it has made no theoretical advances of major importance. It is liv- ing off the conceptual capital of its ancestors, adding very little, save a certain empirical enrichment, to it. The second is that it draws what concepts it does use from a very narrowly defined intellectual tradition. There is Durkheim, Weber, Freud, or Malinowski, and in any particular work the approach of one or two of these transcendent figures is fol- lowed, with but a few marginal corrections necessitated by the natural tendency to excess of seminal minds or by the expanded body of reli- able descriptive data. But virtually no one even thinks of looking elsewhere—to philosophy, history, law, literature, or the "harder" 88 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES sciences—as these men themselves looked, for analytical ideas. And it occurs to me, also, that these two curious characteristics are not unre- lated. If the anthropological study of religion is in fact in a state of general stagnation, I doubt that it will be set going again by producing more minor variations on classical theoretical themes. Yet one more meticu- lous case in point for such well-established propositions as that ancestor worship supports the jural authority of elders, that initiation rites are means for the establishment of sexual identity and adult status, that rit- ual groupings reflect political oppositions, or that myths provide char- ters for social institutions and rationalizations of social privilege, may well finally convince a great many people, both inside the profession and out, that anthropologists are, like theologians, firmly dedicated to proving the indubitable. In art, this solemn reduplication of the achieve- ments of accepted masters is called academicism; and I think this is the proper name for our malady also. Only if we abandon, in a phrase of Leo Steinberg's, that sweet sense of accomplishment which comes from parading habitual skills and address ourselves to problems sufficiently unclarified as to make discovery possible, can we hope to achieve work which will not just reincarnate that of the great men of the first quarter of this century, but match it. 1 The way to do this is not to abandon the established traditions of so- cial anthropology in this field, but to widen them. At least four of the contributions of the men who, as I say, dominate our thought to the point of parochializing it—Durkheim's discussion of the nature of the sacred, Weber's Verstehenden methodology, Freud's parallel between personal rituals and collective ones, and Malinowski's exploration of the distinction between religion and common sense—seem to me inevitable starting-points for any useful anthropological theory of religion. But they are starting-points only. To move beyond them we must place them in a much broader context of contemporary thought than they, in and of themselves, encompass. The dangers of such a procedure are obvious: arbitrary eclecticism, superficial theory-mongering, and sheer intellec- tual confusion. But I, at least, can see no other road of escape from what, referring to anthropology more generally, Janowitz has called the dead hand of competence.2 1 L. Steinberg, "The Eye Is Part of the Mind," Partisan Review 70 (1953): 194-212. 2 M. Janowitz. "Anthropology and the Social Sciences," Current Anthropology 4(I963):I39, 146-154. Religion As a Cultural System 89 In working toward such an expansion of the conceptual envelope in which our studies take place, one can, of course, move in a great num- ber of directions; and perhaps the most important initial problem is to avoid setting out, like Stephen Leacock's mounted policeman, in all of them at once. For my pan, I shall confine my effort to developing what, following Parsons and Shils, I refer to as the cultural dimension of reli- gious analysis.3 The term "culture" has by now acquired a certain aura of ill-repute in social anthropological circles because of the multiplicity of its referents and the studied vagueness with which it has all too often been invoked. (Though why it should suffer more for these reasons than "social structure" or "personality" is something I do not entirely under- stand.) In any case, the culture concept to which I adhere has neither multiple referents nor, so far as I can see, any unusual ambiguity: it de- notes an historically transmitted pattern of meanings embodied in sym- bols, a system of inherited conceptions expressed in symbolic forms by means of which men communicate, perpetuate, and develop their knowledge about and attitudes toward life. Of course, terms such as "meaning," "symbol," and "conception" cry out for explication. But that is precisely where the widening, the broadening, and the expanding come in. If Langer is right that "the concept of meaning, in all its varie- ties, is the dominant philosophical concept of our time," that "sign, symbol, denotation, signification, communication... are our (intellec- tual] stock in trade," it is perhaps time that social anthropology, and particularly that part of it concerned with the study of religion, became aware of the fact.4 II As we are to deal with meaning, let us begin with a paradigm: viz., that sacred symbols function to synthesize a people's ethos—the tone, char- acter, and quality of their life, its moral and aesthetic style and mood —and their world view—the picture they have of the way things in sheer actuality are, their most comprehensive ideas of order. In reli- gious belief and practice a group's ethos is rendered intellectually rea- 3 T. Parsons and E. Shils. Toward a General Theory of Action (Cambridge, Mass., 1951). 4 S. Langer, Philosophical Sketches (Baltimore, 1962). 90 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES sonable by being shown to represent a way of life ideally adapted to the actual state of affairs the world view describes, while the world view is rendered emotionally convincing by being presented as an image of an actual state of affairs peculiarly well-arranged to accommodate such a way of life. This confrontation and mutual confirmation has two funda- mental effects. On the one hand, it objectivizes moral and aesthetic preferences by depicting them as the imposed conditions of life implicit in a world with a particular structure, as mere common sense given the unalterable shape of reality. On the other, it supports these received be- liefs about the world's body by invoking deeply felt moral and aesthetic sentiments as experiential evidence for their truth. Religious symbols formulate a basic congruence between a particular style of life and a specific (if, most often, implicit) metaphysic, and in so doing sustain each with the borrowed authority of the other. Phrasing aside, this much may perhaps be granted. The notion that religion tunes human actions to an envisaged cosmic order and projects images of cosmic order onto the plane of human experience is hardly novel. But it is hardly investigated either, so that we have very little idea of how, in empirical terms, this particular miracle is accomplished. We just know that it is done, annually, weekly, daily, for some people almost hourly; and we have an enormous ethnographic literature to demonstrate it. But the theoretical framework which would enable us to provide an analytic account of it, an account of the son we can provide for lineage segmentation, political succession, labor exchange, or the so- cialization of the child, does not exist. Let us, therefore, reduce our paradigm to a definition, for, although it is notorious that definitions establish nothing, in themselves they do, if they are carefully enough constructed, provide a useful orientation, or reorientation, of thought, such that an extended unpacking of them can be an effective way of developing and controlling a novel line of in- quiry. They have the useful virtue of cxplicitness: they commit them- selves in a way discursive prose, which, in this field especially, is always liable to substitute rhetoric for argument, does not. Without further ado, then, a religion is: (1) a system of symbols which acts to (2) establish powerful, pervasive, and long-lasting moods and motivations in men by (3) formulating conceptions of a general order of existence and (4) clothing these conceptions with such an aura of factuality that (5) the moods and motivations seem uniquely real- istic. Religion As a Cultural System 91 a system of symbols which acts to... Such a tremendous weight is being put on the term "symbol" here that our first move must be to decide with some precision what we are going to mean by it. This is no easy task, for, rather like "culture," "symbol" has been used to refer to a great variety of things, often a number of them at the same time. In some hands it is used for anything which signifies something else to someone: dark clouds are the symbolic precursors of an on-coming rain. In others it is used only for explicitly conventional signs of one sort or another: a red flag is a symbol of danger, a white of surrender. In others it is confined to something which expresses in an oblique and figurative manner that which cannot be stated in a direct and literal one, so that there are symbols in poetry but not in science, and symbolic logic is misnamed. In yet others, however, it is used for any object, act, event, quality, or relation which serves as a vehicle.for a conception— the conception is the symbol's "meaning"—and that is the approach I shall follow here.5 The number 6, written, imagined, laid out as a row of stones, or even punched into the program tapes of a computer, is a symbol. But so also is the Cross, talked about, visualized, shaped wor- riedly in air or fondly fingered at the neck, the expanse of painted can- vas called "Guernica" or the bit of painted stone called a churinga, the word "reality," or even the morpheme "-ing." They are all symbols, or at least symbolic elements, because they are tangible formulations of notions, abstractions from experience fixed in perceptible forms, con- crete embodiments of ideas, attitudes, judgments, longings, or beliefs. To undertake the study of cultural activity—activity in which symbol- ism forms the positive content—is thus not to abandon social analysis for a Platonic cave of shadows, to enter into a mentalistic world of in- trospective psychology or, worse, speculative philosophy, and wander there forever in a haze of "Cognitions," "Affections," "Conations," and other elusive entities. Cultural acts, the construction, apprehension, and utilization of symbolic forms, are social events like any other; they are as public as marriage and as observable as agriculture. They are not, however, exactly the same thing; or, more precisely, the symbolic dimension of social events is, like the psychological, itself theoretically abstractable from those events as empirical totalities. There is still, to paraphrase a remark of Kenneth Burke's, a difference 5 S. Langer, Philosophy in a New Key, 4th ed. (Cambridge. Mass., I960). 92 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES between building a house and drawing up a plan for building a house, and reading a poem about having children by marriage is not quite the same thing as having children by marriage.6 Even though the building of the house may proceed under the guidance of the plan or—a less likely occurrence—the having of children may be motivated by a read- ing of the poem, there is something to be said for not confusing our traffic with symbols with our traffic with objects or human beings, for these latter are not in themselves symbols, however often they may function as such.7 No matter how deeply interfused the cultural, the so- cial, and the psychological may be in the everyday life of houses, farms, poems, and marriages, it is useful to distinguish them in analysis, and, so doing, to isolate the generic traits of each against the normalized background of the other two. So far as culture patterns, that is, systems or complexes of symbols, are concerned, the generic trait which is of first importance for us here is that they are extrinsic sources of information. By "extrinsic," I mean only that—unlike genes, for example—they lie outside the boundaries of the individual organism as such in that intersubjective world of com- mon understandings into which all human individuals are born, in which they pursue their separate careers, and which they leave persist- ing behind them after they die. By "sources of information," I mean only that—like genes—they provide a blueprint or template in terms of which processes external to themselves can be given a definite form. As the order of bases in a strand of DNA forms a coded program, a set of instructions, or a recipe, for the synthesis of the structurally complex proteins which shape organic functioning, so culture patterns provide such programs for the institution of the social and psychological pro- cesses which shape public behavior. Though the sort of information and the mode of its transmission are vastly different in the two cases, this comparison of gene and symbol is more than a strained analogy of the familiar "social heredity" sort. It is actually a substantial relationship, for it is precisely because of the fact that genetically programmed pro- cesses are so highly generalized in men, as compared with lower ani- 6 K. Burke, The Philosophy of Literary Form (Baton Rouge, La.: Louisiana State University Press, 1941), p. 9. 7 The reverse mistake, especially common among neo-Kantians such as Cas- sirer, of taking symbols to be identical with, or "constitutive of," their referents is equally pernicious. (Cf. E. Cassirer, The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms (New Haven: 1953-1957), 3 vols.) "One can point to the moon with one's finger," some, probably well-invented, Zen Master is supposed to have said, "but to take one's finger f or the moon is to be a fool." Religion As a Cultural System 93 mals, that culturally programmed ones are so important; only because human behavior is so loosely determined by intrinsic sources of infor- mation that extrinsic sources are so vital. To build a dam a beaver needs only an appropriate site and the proper materials—his mode of procedure is shaped by his physiology. But man, whose genes are silent on the building trades, needs also a conception of what it is to build a dam, a conception he can get only from some symbolic source—a blue- print, a textbook, or a string of speech by someone who already knows how dams are built—or, of course, from manipulating graphic or lin- guistic elements in such a way as to attain for himself a conception of what dams are and how they are built. This point is sometimes put in the form of an argument that cultural patterns are "models," that they are sets of symbols whose relations to one another "model" relations among entities, processes or what-have- you in physical, organic, social, or psychological systems by "parallel- ing," "imitating," or "simulating" them.8 The term "model" has, how- ever, two senses—an "of" sense and a "for" sense—and though these are but aspects of the same basic concept they are very much worth dis- tinguishing for analytic purposes. In the first, what is stressed is the ma- nipulation of symbol structures so as to bring them, more or less closely, into parallel with the pre-established nonsymbolic system, as when we grasp how dams work by developing a theory of hydraulics or constructing a flow chart. The theory or chart models physical relation- ships in such a way—that is, by expressing their structure in synoptic form—as to render them apprehensible; it is a model of "reality." In the second, what is stressed is the manipulation of the nonsymbolic sys- tems in terms of the relationships expressed in the symbolic, as when we construct a dam according to the specifications implied in an hy- draulic theory or the conclusions drawn from a flow chart. Here, the theory is a model under whose guidance physical relationships are orga- nized: it is a model for "reality." For psychological and social systems, and for cultural models that we would not ordinarily refer to as "theo- ries," but rather as "doctrines," "melodies," or "rites," the case is in no way different. Unlike genes, and other nonsymbolic information sources, which are only models for, not models of, culture patterns have an intrinsic double aspect: they give meaning, that is, objective concep- tual form, to social and psychological reality both by shaping them- selves to it and by shaping it to themselves. 8 K. Craik, The Nature of Explanation (Cambridge, 1952). 94 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES It is, in fact, this double aspect which sets true symbols off from other sorts of significative forms. Models for are found, as the gene ex- ample suggests, through the whole order of nature; for wherever there is a communication of pattern, such programs are, in simple logic, re- quired. Among animals, imprint learning is perhaps the most striking example, because what such learning involves is the automatic presenta- tion of an appropriate sequence of behavior by a model animal in the presence of a learning animal which serves, equally automatically, to call out and stabilize a certain set of responses genetically built into the learning animal.9 The communicative dance of two bees, one of which has found nectar and the other of which seeks it, is another, somewhat different, more complexly coded, example.10 Craik has even suggested that the thin trickle of water which first finds its way down from a mountain spring to the sea and smooths a little channel for the greater volume of water that follows after it plays a sort of model for func- tion.11 But models of—linguistic, graphic, mechanical, natural, etc., processes which function not to provide sources of information in terms of which other processes can be patterned, but to represent those pat- terned processes as such, to express their structure in an alternative medium—are much rarer and may perhaps be confined, among living animals, to man. The perception of the structural congruence between one set of processes, activities, relations, entities, and so on, and an- other set for which it acts as a program, so that the program can be taken as a representation, or conception—a symbol—of the pro- grammed, is the essence of human thought. The intertransposability of models for and models of which symbolic formulation makes possible is the distinctive characteristic of our mentality.... to establish powerful, pervasive, and long-lasting moods and motivations in men by... So far as religious symbols and symbol systems are concerned this in- tertransposability is clear. The endurance, courage, independence, per- severance, and passionate willfulness in which the vision quest practices the Plains Indian are the same flamboyant virtues by which he attempts 9 K. Lorenz, King Salomon's Ring (London. 1952). 10 K. von Frisch, "Dialects in the Language of the Bees," Scientific American. August 1962. 11 Craik, Nature of Explanation. Religion As a Cultural System 95 to live: while achieving a sense of revelation he stabilizes a sense of direction.12 The consciousness of defaulted obligation, secreted guilt, and, when a confession is obtained, public shame in which Manus' se- ance rehearses him are the same sentiments that underlie the sort of duty ethic by which his property-conscious society is maintained: the gaining of an absolution involves the forging of a conscience.l3 And the same self-discipline which rewards a Javanese mystic staring fixedly into the flame of a lamp with what he takes to be an intimation of di- vinity drills him in that rigorous control of emotional expression which is necessary to a man who would follow a quietistic style of life.14 Whether one sees the conception of a personal guardian spirit, a family tutelary, or an immanent God as synoptic formulations of the character of reality or as templates for producing reality with such a character seems largely arbitrary, a matter of which aspect, the model of or model for, one wants for the moment to bring into focus. The concrete sym- bols involved—one or another mythological figure materializing in the wilderness, the skull of the deceased household head hanging censo- riously in the rafters, or a disembodied "voice in the stillness" sound- lessly chanting enigmatic classical poetry—point in either direction. They both express the world's climate and shape it. They shape it by inducing in the worshipper a certain distinctive set of dispositions (tendencies, capacities, propensities, skills, habits, liabil- ities, pronenesses) which lend a chronic character to the flow of his ac- tivity and the quality of his experience. A disposition describes not an activity or an occurrence but a probability of an activity being per- formed or an occurrence occurring in certain circumstances: "When a cow is said to be a ruminant, or a man is said to be a cigarette-smoker, it is not being said that the cow is ruminating now or that the man is smoking a cigarette now. To be a ruminant is to tend to ruminate from time to time, and to be a cigarette-smoker is to be in the habit of smok- ing cigarettes." 15 Similarly, to be pious is not to be performing some- thing we would call an act of piety, but to be liable to perform such acts. So, too, with the Plains Indian's bravura, the Manus' compunc- tiousness, or the Javanese's quietism, which, in their contexts, form the substance of piety. The virtue of this sort of view of what are usually 12 R. H. Lowie, Primitive Religion (New York, 1924). 13 R. F. Fortune. Manus Religion (Philadelphia, 1935). 14 C. Geertz. The Religion of Java (Glencoe,111., I960). 15 G. Ryle. The Concept of Mind (London and New York. 1949). 96 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES called "mental traits" or, if the Cartesianism is unavowed, "psychologi- cal forces" (both unobjectionable enough terms in themselves) is that it gets them out of any dim and inaccessible realm of private sensation into that same well-lit world of observables in which reside the brittle- ness of glass, the inflammability of paper, and, to return to the meta- phor, the dampness of England. So far as religious activities are concerned (and learning a myth by heart is as much a religious activity as detaching one's finger at the knuckle), two somewhat different sorts of disposition are induced by them: moods and motivations. A motivation is a persisting tendency, a chronic inclination to per- form certain sorts of acts and experience certain sorts of feeling in cer- tain sorts of situations, the "sorts" being commonly very heterogenous and rather ill-defined classes in all three cases: On hearing that a man is vain [i.e.. motivated by vanity] we expect him to behave in certain ways, namely to talk a lot about himself, to cleave to the society of the eminent, to reject criticisms, to seek the footlights and to dis- engage himself from conversations about (he merits of others. We expect him to indulge in roseate daydreams about his own successes, to avoid re- calling past failures and to plan for his own advancement. To be vain is to tend to act in these and innumerable other kindred ways. Certainly we also expect the vain man to feel certain pangs and flutters in certain situations; we expect him to have an acute sinking feeling when an eminent person for- gets his name, and to feel buoyant of heart and light of toe on hearing of the misfortunes of his rivals. But feelings of pique and buoyancy are not more directly indicative of vanity than are public acts of boasting or private acts of daydreaming. 16 Similarly for any motivations. As a motive, "flamboyant courage" con- sists in such enduring propensities as to fast in the wilderness, to con- duct solitary raids on enemy camps, and to thrill to the thought of counting coup. "Moral circumspection" consists in such ingrained ten- dencies as to honor onerous promises, to confess secret sins in the face of severe public disapproval, and to feel guilty when vague and general- ized accusations are made at seances. And "dispassionate tranquility" consists in such persistent inclinations as to maintain one's poise come hell or high water, to experience distaste in the presence of even moder- ate emotional displays, and to indulge in contentless contemplations of featureless objects. Motives are thus neither acts (that is, intentional be- 16 Ibid., p. 86. Quoted by permission of Barnes & Noble Books and Hutchinson Publishing Group Ltd. Religion As a Cultural System 97 haviors) nor feelings, but liabilities to perform particular classes of act or have particular classes of feeling. And when we say that a man is re- ligious, that is, motivated by religion, this is at least pan—though only part—of what we mean. Another part of what we mean is that he has, when properly stimu- lated, a susceptibility to fall into certain moods, moods we sometimes lump together under such covering terms as "reverential," "solemn," or "worshipful." Such generalized rubrics actually conceal, however, the enormous empirical variousness of the dispositions involved, and, in fact, tend to assimilate them to the unusually grave tone of most of our own religious life. The moods that sacred symbols induce, at different times and in different places, range from exultation to melancholy, from self-confidence to self-pity, from an incorrigible playfulness to a bland listlessness—to say nothing of the erogenous power of so many of the world's myths and rituals. No more than there is a single sort of motiva- tion one can call piety is there a single sort of mood one can call wor- shipful. The major difference between moods and motivations is that where the latter are, so to speak, vectorial qualities, the former are merely sca- lar. Motives have a directional cast, they describe a certain overall course, gravitate toward certain, usually temporary, consummations. But moods vary only as to intensity: they go nowhere. They spring from certain circumstances but they are responsive to no ends. Like fogs, they just settle and lift; like scents, suffuse and evaporate. When present they are totalistic: if one is sad everything and everybody seems dreary; if one is gay, everything and everybody seems splendid. Thus, though a man can be vain, brave, willful, and independent at the same time, he can't very well be playful and listless, or exultant and melancholy, at the same time. 17 Further, where motives persist for more or less ex- tended periods of time, moods merely recur with greater or lesser fre- quency, coming and going for what are often quite unfathomable rea- sons. But perhaps the most important difference, so far as we are concerned, between moods and motivations is that motivations are "made meaningful" with reference to the ends toward which they are conceived to conduce, whereas moods are "made meaningful" with ref- erence to the conditions from which they are conceived to spring. We interpret motives in terms of their consummations, but we interpret moods in terms of their sources. We say that a person is industrious be- 17 Ibid., p. 99. 98 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES cause he wishes to succeed; we say that a person is worried because he is conscious of the hanging threat of nuclear holocaust. And this is no less the case when the interpretations are ultimate. Charity becomes Christian charity when it is enclosed in a conception of God's purposes; optimism is Christian optimism when it is grounded in a particular con- ception of God's nature. The assiduity of the Navaho finds its rationale in a belief that, since "reality" operates mechanically, it is coercible; their chronic fearfulness finds its rationale in a conviction that, however "reality" operates, it is both enormously powerful and terribly danger- ous.18... by formulating conceptions of a general order of existence and... That the symbols or symbol systems which induce and define disposi- tions we set off as religious and those which place those dispositions in a cosmic framework are the same symbols ought to occasion no sur- prise. For what else do we mean by saying that a particular mood of awe is religious and not secular, except that it springs from entertaining a conception of all-pervading vitality like mana and not from a visit to the Grand Canyon? Or that a particular case of asceticism is an exam- ple of a religious motivation, except that it is directed toward the achievement of an unconditioned end like nirvana and not a conditioned one like weight-reduction? If sacred symbols did not at one and the same time induce dispositions in human beings and formulate, however obliquely, inarticulately, or unsystematically, general ideas of order, then the empirical differentia of religious activity or religious experi- ence would not exist. A man can indeed be said to be "religious" about golf, but not merely if he pursues it with passion and plays it on Sun- days: he must also see it as symbolic of some transcendent truths. And the pubescent boy gazing soulfully into the eyes of the pubescent girl in a William Steig cartoon and murmuring, "There is something about you, Ethel, which gives me a sort of religious feeling," is, like most ad- olescents, confused. What any particular religion affirms about the fun- damental nature of reality may be obscure, shallow, or, all too often, perverse; but it must, if it is not to consist of the mere collection of re- 18 C. Kluckhohn. 'The Philosophy of the Navaho Indians," in Ideological Dif- ferences and World Order, ed. F. S. C. Northrop (New Haven, 1949), pp. 356-384. Religion As a Cultural System 99 ceived practices and conventional sentiments we usually refer to as mor- alism, affirm something. If one were to essay a minimal definition of religion today, it would perhaps not be Tylor's famous "belief in spiri- tual beings," to which Goody, wearied of theoretical subtleties, has lately urged us to return, but rather what Salvador de Madariaga has called "the relatively modest dogma that God is not mad." 19 Usually, of course, religions affirm very much more than this: we be- lieve, as James remarked, all that we can and would believe everything if we only could.20 The thing we seem least able to tolerate is a threat to our powers of conception, a suggestion that our ability to create, grasp, and use symbols may fail us, for were this to happen, we would be more helpless, as I have already pointed out, than the beavers. The ex- treme generality, diffuseness, and variability of man's innate (that is, ge- netically programmed) response capacities means that without the assis- tance of cultural patterns he would be functionally incomplete, not merely a talented ape who had, like some underprivileged child, unfor- tunately been prevented from realizing his full potentialities, but a kind of formless monster with neither sense of direction nor power of self- control, a chaos of spasmodic impulses and vague emotions. Man de- pends upon symbols and symbol systems with a dependence so great as to be decisive for his creatural viability and, as a result, his sensitivity to even the remotest indication that they may prove unable to cope with one or another aspect of experience raises within him the gravest sort of anxiety: [Man] can adapt himself somehow to anything his imagination can cope with; but he cannot deal with Chaos. Because his characteristic function and highest asset is conception, his greatest fright is to meet what he cannot construe—the "uncanny," as it is popularly called. It need not be a new ob- ject; we do meet new things, and "understand" them promptly, if tenta- tively, by the nearest analogy, when our minds are functioning freely; but under mental stress even perfectly familiar things may become suddenly dis- organized and give us the horrors. Therefore our most important assets are always the symbols of our general orientation in nature, on the earth, in so- ciety, and in what we are doing: the symbols of our Weltanschauung and Lebensanschauung. Consequently, in a primitive society, a daily ritual is in- corporated in common activities, in eating, washing, fire-making, etc., as well as in pure ceremonial; because the need of reasserting the tribal morale and recognizing its cosmic conditions is constantly felt. In Christian Europe 19 J. Goody, "Religion and Ritual: The Definition Problem," British Journal of Piychology 12 (196I):143-I64. 20 W. James, The Principles of Psychology, 2 vols. (New York. 1904). 100 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES the Church brought men daily (in some orders even hourly) to their knees, to enact if not to contemplate their assent to the ultimate concepts.21 There are at least three points where chaos—a tumult of events which lack not just interpretations but interpretability—threatens to break in upon man: at the limits of his analytic capacities, at the limits of his powers of endurance, and at the limits of his moral insight. Baf- flement, suffering, and a sense of intractable ethical paradox are all, if they become intense enough or are sustained long enough, radical chal- lenges to the proposition that life is comprehensible and that we can, by taking thought, orient ourselves effectively within it—challenges with which any religion, however "primitive," which hopes to persist must attempt somehow to cope. Of the three issues, it is the first which has been least investigated by modern social anthropologists (though Evans-Pritchard's classic discus- sion of why granaries fall on some Azande and not on others, is a nota- ble exception).22 Even to consider people's religious beliefs as attempts to bring anomalous events or experiences—death, dreams, mental fugues, volcanic eruptions, or marital infidelity—within the circle of the at least potentially explicable seems to smack of Tyloreanism or worse. But it does appear to be a fact that at least some men—in all probabil- ity, most men—are unable to leave unclarified problems of analysis merely unclarified, just to look at the stranger features of the world's landscape in dumb astonishment or bland apathy without trying to de- velop, however fantastic, inconsistent, or simple-minded, some notions as to how such features might be reconciled with the more ordinary de- liverances of experience. Any chronic failure of one's explanatory appa- ratus, the complex of received culture patterns (common sense, science, philosophical speculation, myth) one has for mapping the empirical world, to explain things which cry out for explanation tends to lead to a deep disquiet—a tendency rather more widespread and a disquiet rather deeper than we have sometimes supposed since the pseudoscience view of religious belief was, quite rightfully, deposed. After all, even that high priest of heroic atheism. Lord Russell, once remarked that al- though the problem of the existence of God had never bothered him, the ambiguity of certain mathematical axioms had threatened to unhinge his mind. And Einstein's profound dissatisfaction with quantum me- 21 Langer. Philosophy in a New Key, p. 287. Italics in original. 22 E. Evans-Pritchard. Wlichraft. Oracles and Magic Among the Azonde (Ox- ford, 1937). Religion As a Cultural System 101 chanics was based on a—surely religious—inability to believe that, as he put it, God plays dice with the universe. But this quest for lucidity and the rush of metaphysical anxiety that occurs when empirical phenomena threaten to remain intransigently opaque is found on much humbler intellectual levels. Certainly, I was struck in my own work, much more than I had at all expected to be, by the degree to which my more animistically inclined informants behaved like true Tyloreans. They seemed to be constantly using their beliefs to "explain" phenomena: or, more accurately, to convince themselves that the phenomena were explainable within the accepted scheme of things, for they commonly had only a minimal attachment to the particular soul possession, emotional disequilibrium, taboo infringement, or bewitch- ment hypothesis they advanced and were all too ready to abandon it for some other, in the same genre, which struck them as more plausible given the facts of the case. What they were not ready to do was aban- don it for no other hypothesis at all; to leave events to themselves. And what is more, they adopted this nervous cognitive stance with respect to phenomena which had no immediate practical bearing on their own lives, or for that matter on anyone's. When a peculiarly shaped, rather large toadstool grew up in a carpenter's house in the short space of a few days (or, some said, a few hours), people came from miles around to see it, and everyone had some sort of explanation —some animist, some animatist, some not quite either—for it. Yet it would be hard to argue that the toadstool had any social value in Rad- cliffe-Brown's sense, or was connected in any way with anything which did and for which it could have been standing proxy, like the Andaman cicada.23 Toadstools play about the same role in Javanese life as they do in ours, and in the ordinary course of things Javanese have about as much interest in them as we do. It was just that this one was "odd," "strange," "uncanny"—aneh. And the odd, strange, and uncanny sim- ply must be accounted for—or, again, the conviction that it could be accounted for sustained. One does not shrug off a toadstool which grows five times as fast as a toadstool has any right to grow. In the broadest sense the "strange" toadstool did have implications, and criti- cal ones, for those who heard about it. It threatened their most general ability to understand the world, raised the uncomfortable question of whether the beliefs which they held about nature were workable, the standards of truth they used valid. 23 A. R. Radcliffe-Brown, Structure and Function in Primitive Society (Glen- coe,. III., 1952). 102 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES Nor is this to argue that it is only, or even mainly, sudden eruptions of extraordinary events which engender in man the disquieting sense that his cognitive resources may prove unavailing or that this intuition appears only in its acute form. More commonly it is a persistent, con- stantly re-experienced difficulty in grasping certain aspects of nature, self, and society, in bringing certain elusive phenomena within the sphere of culturally formulatable fact, which renders man chronically uneasy and toward which a more equable flow of diagnostic symbols is consequently directed. It is what lies beyond a relatively fixed frontier of accredited knowledge that, looming as. a constant background to the daily round of practical life, sets ordinary human experience in a per- manent context of metaphysical concern and raises the dim, back-of- the-mind suspicions that one may be adrift in an absurd world: Another subject which is matter for this characteristic intellectual enquiry [among the latmul] is the nature of ripples and waves on the surface of water. It is said secretly that men, pigs, trees, grass—all the objects in the world—are only patterns of waves. Indeed there seems to be some agree- ment about this, although it perhaps conflicts with the theory of reincarna- tion, according to which the ghost of the dead is blown as a mist by the East Wind up the river and into the womb of the deceased's son's wife. Be that as it may—there is still the question of how ripples and waves are caused. The clan which claims the East Wind as a totem is clear enough about this: the Wind with her mosquito fan causes the waves. But other clans have personified the waves and say that they are a person (Konlum- mali) independent of the wind. Other clans, again, have other theories. On one occasion I took some latmul natives down to the coast and found one of them silting by himself gazing with rapt attention at the sea. It was a windless day, but a slow swell was breaking on the beach. Among the to- temic ancestors of his clan he counted a personified slit gong who had floated down the river to the sea and who was believed to cause the waves. He was gazing at the waves which were heaving and breaking when no wind was blowing, demonstrating the truth of his clan myth.24 24 G. Bateson. Naven, 2nd ed. (Stanford, 1958). That the chronic and acute forms of this sort of cognitive concern are closely interrelated, and that responses to the more unusual occasion of it are patterned on responses established in cop- ing with the more usual is also clear from Bateson's description, however, as he goes on to say: "On another occasion I invited one of my informants to writness the development of photographic plates. I first desensitized the plates and then developed them in an open dish in moderate light, so that my informant was able to see the gradual appearance of the images. He was much interested, and then days later made me promise never to show this process to members of other clans. Kontum-mali was one of his ancestors, and he saw in the process of photo- graphic development the actual embodiment of ripples into images, and regarded this as a demonstration of the clan's secret." Religion As a Cultural System 103 The second experiential challenge in whose face the meaningfulness of a particular pattern of life threatens to dissolve into a chaos of thing- less names and nameless things—the problem of suffering—has been rather more investigated, or at least described, mainly because of the great amount of attention given in works on tribal religion to what are perhaps its two main loci: illness and mourning. Yet for all the fasci- nated interest in the emotional aura that surrounds these extreme situa- tions, there has been, with a few exceptions such as Lienhardt's recent discussion of Dinka divining, little conceptual advance over the sort of crude confidence-type theory set forth by Malinowski: viz., that religion helps one to endure "situations of emotional stress" by "open [ing] up escapes from such situations and such impasses as offer no empirical way out except by ritual and belief into the domain of the supernatural."25 The inadequacy of this "theology of optimism," as Nadel rather dryly called it, is, of course, radical.26 Over its career reli- gion has probably disturbed men as much as it has cheered them; forced them into a head-on, unblinking confrontation of the fact that they are born to trouble as often as it has enabled them to avoid such a confron- tation by projecting them into sort of infantile fairy-tale worlds where —Malinowski again—"hope cannot fail nor desire deceive." 27 With the possible exception of Christian Science, there are few if any reli- gious traditions, "great" or "little," in which the proposition that life hurts is not strenuously affirmed, and in some it is virtually glorified: She was an old [Ba-lia] woman of a family with a long genealogy. Leza, "the Besetting One", stretched out his hand against the family. He slew her mother and father while she was yet a child, and in the course of years all connected with her perished. She said to herself, "Surely I shall keep those who sit on my thighs." But no, even they, the children of her children, were taken from her.... Then came into her heart a desperate resolution to find God and to ask the meaning of it all.... So she began to travel, going through country after country, always with the thought in her mind: "I shall come to where the earth ends and there I shall find a road to God and I shall ask him: 'What have I done to thee that thou afflictest me in this manner?' " She never found where the earth ends, but though disappointed she did not give up her search, and as she passed through the different countries (hey asked her. "What have you come for. old woman?" And the 25 G. Lienhardt, Divinity and Experience (Oxford, 1961), p. 151ff; B. Mali- nowski. Magic. Science and Religion (Boston, 1948), p. 67. 26 S. F. Nadel, "Malinowski on Mafic and Religion," in Man and Culture, ed. R. 27 Firth (London, 1957). pp. 189-208. Malinowski, Magic. Science and Religion (Boston, 1948), p. 67. 104 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES answer would be. "I am seeking Leu." "Seeking Leza! For what?" "My brothers, you ask me! Here in the nations is there one who suffers as I have suffered?" And they would ask again, "How have you suffered?" "In this way. I am alone. As you see me, a solitary old woman; that is how I am!" And they answered. "Yes. we see. That is how you are! Bereaved of friends and husband? In what do you differ from others? The Besetting-One sits on the back of every one of us and we cannot shake him off." She never ob- tained her desire; she died of a broken heart.28 As a religious problem, the problem of suffering is, paradoxically, not how to avoid suffering but how to suffer, how to make of physical pain, personal loss, wordly defeat, or the helpless contemplation of oth- ers' agony something bearable, supportable—something, as we say, suf- ferable. It was in this effort that the Ba-Ila woman—perhaps neces- sarily, perhaps not—failed and, literally not knowing how to feel about what had happened to her, how to suffer, perished in confusion and de- spair. Where the more intellective aspects of what Weber called the Problem of Meaning are a matter affirming the ultimate explicability of experience, the more affective aspects are a matter of affirming its ulti- mate sufferableness. As religion on one side anchors the power of our symbolic resources for formulating analytic ideas in an authoritative conception of the overall shape of reality, so on another side it anchors the power of our, also symbolic, resources for expressing emotions— moods, sentiments, passions, affections, feelings—in a similar concep- tion of its pervasive tenor, its inherent tone and temper. For those able to embrace them, and for so long as they are able to embrace them, re- ligious symbols provide a cosmic guarantee not only for their ability to comprehend the world, but also, comprehending it, to give a precision to their feeling, a definition to their emotions which enables them, mo- rosely or joyfully, grimly or cavalierly, to endure it. Consider in this light the well-known Navaho curing rites usually re- ferred to as "sings." 29 A sing—the Navaho have about sixty different ones for different purposes, but virtually all of them are dedicated to re- moving some sort of physical or mental illness—is a kind of religious psychodrama in which there are three main actors: the "singer" or curer, the patient, and, as a kind of antiphonal chorus, the patient's family and friends. The structure of all the sings, the drama's plot, is 28 C. W. Smith and A. M. Dale, The Ila-Speaking Peoples of Northern Rho- desia (London. 1920). p. I97ff.; quoted in P. Radin, Primitive Man as a Philoso- pher (New York. 1957), pp. 100-101. 29 C. Kluckhohn and D. Leighton. The Navaho (Cambridge. Mass., 1946); C. Reichard. Navaho Religion. 2 vols. (New York. 1950). Religion As a Cultural System 105 quite similar. There are three main acts: a purification of the patient and audience; a statement, by means of repetitive chants and ritual ma- nipulations, of the wish to restore well-being ("harmony") in the pa- tient; an identification of the patient with the Holy People and his con- sequent "cure." The purification rites involve forced sweating, induced vomiting, and so on, to expel the sickness from the patient physically. The chants, which are numberless, consist mainly of simple optative phrases ("may the patient be well," "I am getting better all over," etc.). And, finally, the identification of the patient with the Holy People, and thus with cosmic order generally, is accomplished through the agency of a sand painting depicting the Holy People in one-or another appropriate mythic setting. The singer places the patient on the painting, touching the feet, hands, knees, shoulders, breast, back, and head of the divine figures and then the corresponding parts of the patient, performing thus what is essentially a bodily identification of the human and the divine.30 This is the climax of the sing: the whole curing process may be likened, Reichard says, to a spiritual osmosis in which the illness in man and the power of the deity penetrate the ceremonial membrane in both direc- tions, the former being neutralized by the latter. Sickness seeps out in the sweat, vomit, and other purification rites; health seeps in as the Na- vaho patient touches, through the medium of the singer, the sacred sand painting. Clearly, the symbolism of the sing focuses upon the problem of human suffering and attempts to cope with it by placing it in a mean- ingful context, providing a mode of action through which it can be ex- pressed, being expressed understood, and being understood, endured. The sustaining effect of the sing (and since the commonest disease is tuberculosis, it can in most cases be only sustaining), rests ultimately on its ability to give the stricken person a vocabulary in terms of which to grasp the nature of his distress and relate it to the wider world. Like a calvary, a recitation of Buddha's emergence from his father's palace, or a performance of Oedipus Tyrannos in other religious traditions, a sing is mainly concerned with the presentation of a specific and concrete image of truly human, and so endurable, suffering powerful enough to resist the challenge of emotional meaninglessness raised by the existence of intense and unremovable brute pain. The problem of suffering passes easily into the problem of evil, for if suffering is severe enough it usually, though not always, seems morally undeserved as well, at least to the sufferer. But they are not, however, exactly the same thing—a fact I think Weber, too influenced by the 30 Reichard, Navaho Religion. 106 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES biases of a monotheistic tradition in which, as the various aspects of human experience must be conceived to proceed from a single, volun- taristic source, man's pain reflects directly on God's goodness, did not fully recognize in his generalization of the dilemmas of Christian theod- icy Eastward. For where the problem of suffering is concerned with threats to our ability to put our "undisciplined squads of emotion" into some sort of soldierly order, the problem of evil is concerned with threats to our ability to make sound moral judgments. What is involved in the problem of evil is not the adequacy of our symbolic resources to govern our affective life, but the adequacy of those resources to provide a workable set of ethical criteria, normative guides to govern our action. The vexation here is the gap between things as they are and as they ought to be if our conceptions of right and wrong make sense, the gap between what we deem various individuals deserve and what we see that they get—a phenomenon summed up in that profound quatrain: The rain falls on the just And on the unjust fella; But mainly upon the just. Because the unjust has the just's umbrella. Or if this seems too flippant an expression of an issue that, in some- what different form, animates the Book of Job and the Baghavad Gita, the following classical Javanese poem, known, sung, and repeatedly quoted in Java by virtually everyone over the age of six, puts the point —the discrepancy between moral prescriptions and material rewards, the seeming inconsistency of "is" and "ought":—rather more elegantly: We have lived to see a time without order In which everyone is confused in his mind. One cannot bear to join in the madness, But if he does not do so He will not share in the spoils, And will starve as a result. Yes, God; wrong is wrong: Happy are those who forget. Happier yet those who remember and have deep insight. Nor is it necessary to be theologically self-conscious to be religiously sophisticated. The concern with intractable ethical paradox, the dis- quieting sense that one's moral insight is inadequate to one's moral ex- perience, is as alive on the level of so-called primitive religion as it is on that of the so-called civilized. The set of notions about "division in the world" that Lienhardt describes for the Dinka is a useful case in Religion As a Cultural System 107 31 point. Like so many peoples, the Dinka believe that the sky, where "Divinity" is located, and earth, where man dwells, were at one time contiguous, the sky lying just above the earth and being connected to it by a rope, so that men could move at will between the two realms. There was no death and the first man and woman were permitted but a single grain of millet a day, which was all that they at that time re- quired. One day, the woman—of course—decided, out of greed, to plant more than the permitted grain of millet, and in her avid haste and industry accidentally struck Divinity with the handle of the hoe. Of- fended, he severed the rope, withdrew into the distant sky of today, and left man to labor for his food, to suffer sickness and death, and to expe- rience separation from the source of his being, his Creator. Yet the meaning of this strangely familiar story to the Dinka is, as indeed is Genesis to Jews and Christians, not homiletic but descriptive: Those [Dinka] who have commented on these stories have sometimes made it clear that their sympathies lie with Man in his plight, and draw attention to the smallness of the fault for which Divinity withdrew the benefits of his closeness. The image of striking Divinity with a hoe... often evokes a certain amusement, almost as though the story were indulgently being treated as too childish to explain the consequences attributed to the event. But it is clear that the point of the story of Divinity's withdrawal from men is not to suggest an improving moral judgment on human behaviour. It is to represent a total situation known to the Dinka today. Men now are—as the first man and woman then became—active, self-assertive, inquiring, acquisi- tive. Yet they are also subject to suffering and death, ineffective, ignorant and poor. Life is insecure; human calculations often prove erroneous, and men must often learn by experience that the consequences of their acts are quite other than they may have anticipated or consider equitable. Divinity's withdrawal from Man as the result of a comparatively trifling offence, by human standards, presents the contrast between equitable human judgments and the action of the Power which are held ultimately to control what hap- pens in Dinka life.... To the Dinka, the moral order is ultimately consti- tuted according to principles which often elude men. which experience and tradition in part reveal, and which human action cannot change.... The myth of Divinity's withdrawal then reflects the facts of existence as they are known. The Dinka are in a universe which is largely beyond their control, and where events may contradict the most reasonable human expectations.32 Thus the problem of evil, or perhaps one should say the problem about evil, is in essence the same sort of problem of or about bafflement and the problem of or about suffering. The strange opacity of certain 31 Ibid., pp. 28-55. 32 Ibid. 108 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES empirical events, the dumb senselessness of intense or inexorable pain, and the enigmatic unaccountability of gross iniquity all raise the uncom- fortable suspicion that perhaps the world, and hence man's life in the world, has no genuine order at all—no empirical regularity, no emo- tional form, no moral coherence. And the religious response to this sus- picion is in each case the same: the formulation, by means of symbols, of an image of such a genuine order of the world which will account for, and even celebrate, the perceived ambiguities, puzzles, and para- doxes in human experience. The effort is not to deny the undeniable— that there are unexplained events, that life hurts, or that rain falls upon the just—but to deny that there are inexplicable events, that life is unendurable, and that justice is a mirage. The principles which consti- tute the moral order may indeed often elude men, as Lienhardt puts it, in the same way as fully satisfactory explanations of anomalous events or effective forms for the expression of feeling often elude them. What is important, to a religious man at least, is that this elusiveness be ac- counted for, that it be not the result of the fact that there are no such principles, explanations, or forms, that life is absurd and the attempt to make moral, intellectual, or emotional sense out of experience is boot- less. The Dinka can admit, in fact insist upon, the moral ambiguities and contradictions of life as they live it because these ambiguities and contradictions are seen not as ultimate, but as the "rational," "natural," "logical" (one may choose one's own adjective here, for none of them is truly adequate) outcome of the moral structure of reality which the myth of the withdrawn "Divinity" depicts, or as Lienhardt says, "im- ages." The Problem of Meaning in each of its intergrading aspects (how these aspects in fact intergrade in each particular case, what sort of in- terplay there is between the sense of analytic, emotional, and moral im- potence, seems to me one of the outstanding, and except for Weber un- touched, problems for comparative research in this whole field) it a matter of affirming, or at least recognizing, the inescapability of igno- rance, pain, and injustice on the human plane while simultaneously denying that these irrationalities are characteristic of the world as a whole. And it is in terms of religious symbolism, a symbolism relating man's sphere of existence to a wider sphere within which it is conceived to rest, that both the affirmation and the denial are made.33 33 This is not, however, to say that everyone in every society does this; for as the immortal Don Marquis once remarked, you don't have to have a soul unless Religion As a Cultural System 109... and clothing those conceptions with such an aura of factuality that... There arises here, however, a more profound question: how is it that this denial comes to be believed? How is it that the religious man moves from a troubled perception of experienced disorder to a more or less settled conviction of fundamental order? Just what does "belief mean in a religious context? Of all the problems surrounding attempts to conduct anthropological analysis of religion this is the one that has perhaps been most troublesome and therefore the most often avoided, usually by relegating it to psychology, that raffish outcast discipline to which social anthropologists are forever consigning phenomena they are unable to deal with within the framework of a denatured Durkheimian- ism. But the problem will not go away, it is not "merely" psychological (nothing social is), and no anthropological theory of religion which fails to attack it is worthy of the name. We have been trying to stage Hamlet without the Prince quite long enough. It seems to me that it is best to begin any approach to this issue with frank recognition that religious belief involves not a Baconian induction from everyday experience—for then we should all be agnostics—but rather a prior acceptance of authority which transforms that experience. The existence of bafflement, pain, and moral paradox—of The Problem of Meaning—is one of the things that drives men toward belief in gods, devils, spirits, totemic principles, or the spiritual efficacy of cannibalism (an enfolding sense of beauty or a dazzling perception of power are others), but it is not the basis upon which those beliefs rest, but rather their most important field of application: We point to the state of the world as illustrative of doctrine, but never as evidence for it. So Belsen illustrates a world of original sin, but original sin is not an hypothesis to account for happenings like Belsen. We justify a par- ticular religious belief by showing its place in the total religious conception; we justify a religious belief as a whole by referring to authority. We accept authority because we discover it at some point in the world at which we you really want one. The oft-heard generalization that religion is a human uni- versal embodies a confusion between the probably true (though on present evi- dence improvable) proposition that there is no human society in which cultural patterns that we can, under the present definition or one like it, call religious are totally lacking, and the surely untrue proposition that all men in all societies are, in any meaningful sense of the term, religious. But if the anthropological study of religious commitment is underdeveloped, the anthropological study of religious noncommitment is nonexistent. The anthropology of religion will have come of age when some more subtle Malinowski writes a book called "Belief and Unbe- lief (or even "Faith and Hypocrisy") in a Savage Society." 110 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES worship, at which we accept the lordship of something not ourselves. We do not worship authority, but we accept authority at defining the worshipful. So someone may discover the possibility of worship in the life of the Re- formed Churches and accept the Bible as authoritative; or in the Roman Church and accept papal authority.34 This is, of course, a Christian statement of the matter; but it is not to be despised on that account. In tribal religions authority lies in the per- suasive power of traditional imagery; in mystical ones in the apodictic force of supersensible experience; in charismatic ones in the hypnotic attraction of an extraordinary personality. But the priority of the accep- tance of an authoritative criterion in religious matters over the revela- tion which is conceived to flow from that acceptance is not less com- plete than in scriptural or hieratic ones. The basic axiom underlying what we may perhaps call "the religious perspective" is everywhere the same: he who would know must first believe. But to speak of "the religious perspective" is, by implication, to speak of one perspective among others. A perspective is a mode of seeing, in that extended sense of "see" in which it means "discern," "apprehend," "understand," or "grasp." It is a particular way of look- ing at life, a particular manner of construing the world, as when we speak of an historical perspective, a scientific perspective, an aesthetic perspective, a common-sense perspective, or even the bizarre perspec- tive embodied in dreams and in hallucinations.35 The question then comes down to, first, what is "the religious perspective" generically con- sidered, as differentiated from other perspectives; and second, how do men come to adopt it. 34 A. Maclntyre. The Logical Status of Religious Belief," in Metaphysical Be- liefs. ed. A. Maclntyre (London. 1957), pp. 167-211. 35 The term "attitude'' at in "aesthetic attitude'' or "natural attitude" it an- other, perhapt more common term for what I have here called "perspective." [For the first, tee C. Bell, Art. London, 1914; for the second, though the phrase it originally Husserl's, see A. Schutz, The Problem of Social Reality, vol. I of Collected Papers (The Hague, 1962).] But I have avoided it because of its strong subjectivist connotations, its tendency to place the stress upon a supposed inner state of an actor rather than on a certain sort of relation—a symbolically me- diated one—between an actor and a situation. This is not to say, of course, that a phenomenological analysis of religious experience, if cast in intersubjective, nontrantcendental, genuinely scientific terms (e.g., W. Percy, "Symbol, Con- sciousness and Intersubjectivity," Journal of Philosophy 15 (I958):631-64l). is not essential to a full understanding of religious belief, but merely that that is not the focus of my concern here. "Outlook." "frame of reference," "frame of mind," "orientation," "stance." "mental set," and so on, are other terms sometimes em- ployed, depending upon whether the analyst wishes to stress the social, psycho- logical, or cultural aspects of the matter. Religion As a Cultural System 111 If we place the religious perspective against the background of three of the other major perspectives in terms of which men construe the world—the common-sensical, the scientific, and the aesthetic—its spe- cial character emerges more sharply. What distinguishes common sense as a mode of "seeing" is, as Schutz has pointed out, a simple acceptance of the world, its objects, and its processes as being just what they seem to be—what is sometimes called naive realism—and the pragmatic mo- tive, the wish to act upon that world so as to bend it to one's practical purposes, to master it, or so far as that proves impossible, to adjust to it.36 The world of everyday life, itself, of course, a cultural product, for it is framed in terms of the symbolic conceptions of "stubborn fact" handed down from generation to generation, is the established scene and given object of our actions. Like Mt. Everest it is just there, and the thing to do with it, if one feels the need to do anything with it at all, is to climb it. In the scientific perspective it is precisely this givenness which disappears.37 Deliberate doubt and systematic inquiry, the sus- pension of the pragmatic motive in favor of disinterested observation, the attempt to analyze the world in terms of formal concepts whose re- lationship to the informal conceptions of common sense become in- creasingly problematic—there are the hallmarks of the attempt to grasp the world scientifically. And as for the aesthetic perspective, which under the rubric of "the aesthetic attitude" has been perhaps most ex- quisitely examined, it involves a different sort of suspension of naive realism and practical interest, in that instead of questioning the creden- tials of everyday experience, one merely ignores that experience in favor of an eager dwelling upon appearances, an engrossment in sur- faces, an absorption in things, as we say, "in themselves": "The func- tion of artistic illusion is not 'make-believe'... but the very opposite, disengagement from belief—the contemplation of sensory qualities without their usual meanings of 'here's that chair', 'that's my telephone'... etc. The knowledge that what is before us has no practi- cal significance in the world is what enables us to give attention to its appearance as such." 38 And like the common sensical and the scien- tific (or the historical, the philosophical, and the artistic), this perspec- tive, this "way of seeing" is not the product of some mysterious Carte- sian chemistry, but is induced, mediated, and in fact created by means 36 Schutz, The Problem of Social Reality. 37 Ibid. 38 S. Lamer. Feeling and Form (New York, 1953), p. 49. 112 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES of curious quasi objects—poems, dramas, sculptures, symphonies— which, dissociating themselves from the solid world of common sense, take on the special sort of eloquence only sheer appearances can achieve. The religious perspective differs from the common-sensical in that, as already pointed out, it moves beyond the realities of everyday life to wider ones which correct and complete them, and its defining concern is not action upon those wider realities but acceptance of them, faith in them. It differs from the scientific perspective in that it questions the realities of everyday life not out of an institutionalized scepticism which dissolves the world's givenness into a swirl of probabilistic hypotheses, but in terms of what it takes to be wider, nonhypothetical truths. Rather than detachment, its watchword is commitment; rather than analysis, encounter. And it differs from art in that instead of effecting a disen- gagement from the whole question of factuality, deliberately manufac- turing an air of semblance and illusion, it deepens the concern with fact and seeks to create an aura of utter actuality. It is this sense of the "really real" upon which the religious perspective rests and which the symbolic activities of religion as a cultural system are devoted to pro- ducing, intensifying, and, so far as possible, rendering inviolable by the discordant revelations of secular experience. It is, again, the imbuing of a certain specific complex of symbols—of the metaphysic they formu- late and the style of life they recommend—with a persuasive authority which, from an analytic point of view, is the essence of religious action. Which brings us, at length, to ritual. For it is in ritual—that is, con- secrated behavior—that this conviction that religious conceptions are veridical and that religious directives are sound is somehow generated. It is in some sort of ceremonial form—even if that form be hardly more than the recitation of a myth, the consultation of an oracle, or the decoration of a grave—that the moods and motivations which sacred symbols induce in men and the general conceptions of the order of exis- tence which they formulate for men meet and reinforce one another. In a ritual, the world as lived and the world as imagined, fused under the agency of a single set of symbolic forms, turn out to be the same world, producing thus that idiosyncratic transformation in one's sense of reality to which Santayana refers in my epigraph. Whatever role divine inter- vention may or may not play in the creation of faith—and it is not the business of the scientist to pronounce upon such matters one way or the other—it is, primarily at least, out of the context of concrete acts of re- Religion As a Cultural System 113 ligious observance that religious conviction emerges on the human plane. However, though any religious ritual, no matter how apparently auto- matic or conventional (if it is truly automatic or merely conventional it is not religious), involves this symbolic fusion of ethos and world view, it is mainly certain more elaborate and usually more public ones, ones in which a broad range of moods and motivations on the one hand and of metaphysical conceptions on the other are caught up, which shape the spiritual consciousness of a people. Employing a useful term intro- duced by Singer, we may call these full-blown ceremonies "cultural performances" and note that they represent not only the point at which the dispositional and conceptual aspects of religious life converge for the believer, but also the point at which the interaction between them can be most readily examined by the detached observer: Whenever Madrasi Brahmans (and non-Brahmans, too, for that matter) wished to exhibit to me some feature of Hinduism, they always referred to, or invited me to see, a particular rite or ceremony in the life cycle, in a temple festival, or in the general sphere of religious and cultural perfor- mances. Reflecting on this in the course of my interviews and observations I found that the more abstract generalizations about Hinduism (my own as well as those I heard) could generally be checked, directly or indirectly, against these observable performances.39 Of course, ail cultural performances are not religious performances, and the line between those that are and artistic, or even political, ones is often not so easy to draw in practice, for, like social forms, symbolic forms can serve multiple purposes. But the point is that, paraphrasing slightly, Indians—"and perhaps all peoples"—seem to think of their religion "as encapsulated in these discrete performances which they [can] exhibit to visitors and to themselves." 40 The mode of exhibi- tion is however radically different for the two sorts of witness, a fact seemingly overlooked by those who would argue that "religion is a form of human art." 41 Where for "visitors" religious performances can, in the nature of the case, only be presentations of a particular religious perspective, and thus aesthetically appreciated or scientifically dissected, 39 M. Singer, 'The Cultural Pattern of Indian Civilization," Far Eastern Quar- terly 15(19J5):23-26. 40 M. Singer, "The Great Tradition in a Metropolitan Center: Madras," in Traditional 41 India, ed. M. Singer (Philadelphia, 1958). pp. 140-182. R. Firth, Etements of Social Organization (London and New York, 1951), p. 250. 114 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES for participants they are in addition enactments, materializations, reali- zations of it—not only models of what they believe, but also models for the believing of it. In these plastic dramas men attain their faith as they portray it. As a case in point, let me take a spectacularly theatrical cultural per- formance from Bali—that in which a terrible witch called Rangda en- gages in a ritual combat with an endearing monster called Barong.42 Usually, but not inevitably presented on the occasion of a death temple celebration, the drama consists of a masked dance in which the witch —depicted as a wasted old widow, prostitute, and eater of infants— comes to spread plague and death upon the land and is opposed by the monster—depicted as a kind of cross between a clumsy bear, a silly puppy, and a strutting Chinese dragon. Rangda, danced by a single male, is a hideous figure. Her eyes bulge from her forehead like swollen boils. Her teeth become tusks curving up over her cheeks and fangs protruding down over her chin. Her yellowed hair falls down around her in a matted tangle. Her breasts are dry and pendulous dugs edged with hair, between which hang, like so many sausages, strings of col- ored entrails. Her long red tongue is a stream of fire. And as she dances she splays her dead-white hands, from which protrude ten-inch claw- like fingernails, out in front of her and utters unnerving shrieks of me- tallic laughter. Barong, danced by two men fore-and-aft in vaudeville horse fashion, is another matter. His shaggy sheepdog coat is hung with gold and mica ornaments that glitter in the half-light. He is adorned with flowers, sashes, feathers, mirrors, and a comical beard made from human hair. And though a demon too, his eyes also pop and he snaps his fanged jaws with seemly fierceness when faced with Rangda or other affronts to his dignity; the cluster of tinkling bells which hang from his absurdly arching tail somehow contrives to take most of the edge off his fearfulness. If Rangda is a satanic image, Barong is a farcical one, and their clash is a clash (an inconclusive one) between the malignant and the ludicrous. 42 The Rangda-Barong complex has been extensively described and analyzed by a series of unusually gifted ethnographers and I shall make no attempt to pre- sent it here in more than schematic form. (See, for example, J. Belo, Bali: Rangda and Barong (New York, 1949); J. Belo, Trance in Bali (New York, 1960); B. DeZoete and W. Spies, Dance and Drama in Bali (London, 1938); G. Bateson and M. Mead, Balinese Character (New York, 1942); M. Covarrubias, The Island of Bali (New York, 1937).) Much of my interpretation of the complex rests on personal observations made in Bali during 1957-1958. Religion As a Cultural System 115 This odd counterpoint of implacable malice and low comedy per- vades the whole performance. Rangda, clutching her magical white cloth, moves around in a slow stagger, now pausing immobile in thought or uncertainty, now lurching suddenly forward. The moment of her entry (one sees those terrible long-nailed hands first as she emerges through the split gateway at the top of a short flight of stone stairs) is one of terrific tension when it seems, to a "visitor" at least, that every- one is about to break and run in panic. She herself seems insane with fear and hatred as she screams deprecations at Barong amid the wild clanging of the gamelan. She may in fact go amok. I have myself seen Rangdas hurl themselves headlong into the gamelan or run frantically about in total confusion, being subdued and reoriented only by the com- bined force of a half-dozen spectators; and one hears many tales of amok Rangdas holding a whole village in terror for hours and of imper- sonators becoming permanently deranged by their experiences. But Ba- rong, though he is charged with the same mana-like sacred power (sakti in Balinese) as Rangda, and his impersonators are also entranced, seems to have very great difficulty in being serious. He frolics with his retinue of demons (who add to the gaiety by indelicate pranks of their own), lies down on a metallaphone while it is being played or beats on a drum with his legs, moves in one direction in his front half and another in his rear or bends his segmented body into foolish contortions, brushes flies from his body or sniffs aromas in the air, and generally prances about in paroxysms of narcissistic vanity. The contrast is not absolute, for Rangda is sometimes momentarily comic as when she pretends to polish the mirrors on Barong's coat, and Barong becomes rather more serious after Rangda appears, nervously clacking his jaws at her and ultimately attacking her directly. Nor are the humorous and the horrible always kept rigidly separated, as in that strange scene in one section of the cycle in which several minor witches (disciples of Rangda) toss the corpse of a stillborn child around to the wild amusement of the audi- ence; or another, no less strange, in which the sight of a pregnant woman alternating hysterically between tears and laughter while being knocked about by a group of gravediggers, seems for some reason ex- cruciatingly funny. The twin themes of horror and hilarity find their purest expression in the two protagonists and their endless, indecisive struggle for dominance, but they are woven with deliberate intricacy through the whole texture of the drama. They—or rather the relations between them—are what it is about. 116 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES It is unnecessary to attempt a thoroughgoing description of a Rangda-Barong performance here. Such performances vary widely in detail, consist of several not too closely integrated parts, and in any case are so complex in structure as to defy easy summary. For our purposes, the main point to be stressed is that the drama is, for the Balinese, not merely a spectacle to be watched but a ritual to be enacted. There is no aesthetic distance here separating actors from audience and placing the depicted events in an unenterable world of illusion, and by the time a full-scale Rangda-Barong encounter has been concluded a majority, often nearly all, of the members of the group sponsoring it will have be- come caught up in it not just imaginatively but bodily. In one of Belo's examples I count upwards of seventy-Ave people—men, women, and children—taking part in the activity at some point or other, and thirty to forty participants is in no way unusual. As a performance, the drama is like a high mass, not like a presentation of Murder in the Cathedral: it is a drawing near, not a standing back. In part, this entry into the body of the ritual takes place through the agency of the various supporting roles contained in it—minor witches, demons, various sorts of legendary and mythical figures—which se- lected villagers enact. But mostly it takes place through the agency of an extraordinarily developed capacity for psychological dissociation on the part of a very large segment of the population. A Rangda-Barong strug- gle is inevitably marked by anywhere from three or four to several dozen spectators becoming possessed by one or another demon, falling into violent trances "like firecrackers going off one after the other," 43 and, snatching up krisses, rushing to join the fray. Mass trance, spread- ing like a panic, projects the individual Balinese out of the common- place world in which he usually lives into that most uncommonplace one in which Rangda and Barong live. To become entranced is, for the Balinese, to cross a threshold into another order of existence—the word for trance is nadi, from dadi, often translated "to become" but which might be even more simply rendered as "to be." And even those who, for whatever reasons, do not make this spiritual crossing are caught up in the proceedings, for it is they who must keep the frenzied activities of the entranced from getting out of hand by the application of physical restraint if they are ordinary men, by the sprinkling of holy water and the chanting of spells if they are priests. At its height a Rangda-Barong rite hovers, or at least seems to hover, on the brink of mass amok with 43 Belo. Trance in Bali. Religion As a Cultural System 117 the diminishing band of the unentranced striving desperately (and, it teems, almost always successfully) to control the growing band of the entranced. In its standard form—if it can be said to have a standard form—the performance begins with an appearance of Barong, prancing and preen- ing, as a general prophylactic against what is to follow. Then may come various mythic scenes relating the story—not always precisely the same ones—upon which the performance is based, until finally Barong and then Rangda appear. Their battle begins. Barong drives Rangda back toward the gate of the death temple. But he has not the power to expel her completely, and he is in turn driven back toward the village. At length, when it seems as though Rangda will finally prevail, a number of entranced men rise, krisses in hand, and rush to support Barong. But as they approach Rangda (who has turned her back in meditation), she wheels upon them and, waving her sakti white cloth, leaves them coma- tose on the ground. Rangda then hastily retires (or is carried) to the temple, where she herself collapses, hidden from the aroused crowd which, my informants said, would kill her were it to see her in a help- less state. The Barong moves among the kris dancers and wakens them by snapping his jaws at them or nuzzling them with his beard. As they return, still entranced, to "consciousness," they are enraged by the dis- appearance of Rangda, and unable to attack her they turn their krisses (harmlessly because they are entranced) against their own chests in frus- tration. Usually sheer pandemonium breaks out at this point with mem- bers of the crowd, of both sexes, falling into trance all around the court- yard and rushing out to stab themselves, wrestle with one another, devour live chicks or excrement, wallow convulsively in the mud, and so on, while the nonentranced attempt to relieve them of their krisses and keep them at least minimally in order. In time, the trancers sink, one by one, into coma, from which they are aroused by the priests' holy water and the great battle is over—once more a complete stand-off. Rangda has not been conquered, but neither has she conquered. One place to search for the meaning of this ritual is in the collection of myths, tales, and explicit beliefs which it supposedly enacts. How- ever, not only are these various and variable—for some people Rangda is an incarnation of Durga, Siva's malignant consort; for others she is Queen Mahendradatta, a figure from a court legend set in eleventh century Java; for yet others, the spiritual leader of witches as the Brah- mana Priest is the spiritual leader of men. Notions of who (or "what") 118 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES Barong is are equally diverse and even vaguer—but they seem to play only a secondary role in the Balinese' perception of the drama. It is in the direct encounter with the two figures in the context of the ac- tual performance that the villager comes to know them as, so far as he is concerned, genuine realities. They are, then, not representations of anything, but presences. And when the villagers go into trance they become—nadi—themselves part of the realm in which those presences exist. To ask, as I once did, a man who has been Rangda whether he thinks she is real is to leave oneself open to the suspicion of idiocy. The acceptance of authority that underlies the religious perspective that the ritual embodies thus flows from the enactment of the ritual it- self. By inducing a set of moods and motivations—an ethos—and de- fining an image of cosmic order—a world view—by means of a single set of symbols, the performance makes the model for and model of as- pects of religious belief mere transpositions of one another. Rangda evokes fear (as well as hatred, disgust, cruelty, horror, and, though I have not been able to treat the sexual aspects of the performance here, lust); but she also depicts it: The fascination which the figure of the Witch holds for the Balinese imagi- nation can only be explained when it is recognized that the Witch is not only a fear inspiring figure, but that she is Fear. Her hands with their long menacing finger-nails do not clutch and claw at her victims, although chil- dren who play at being witches do curl their hands in such gestures. But the Witch herself spreads her arms with palms out and her finger flexed back- ward, in the gesture the Balinese call kapar. a term which they apply to the sudden startled reaction of a man who falls from a tree.... Only when we sec the Witch as herself afraid, as well as frightening, is it possible to ex- plain her appeal, and the pathos which surrounds her as she dances, hairy, forbidding, tusked and alone, giving her occasional high eerie laugh. 44 And on his side Barong not only induces laughter, he incarnates the Ba- linese version of the comic spirit—a distinctive combination of playful- ness, exhibitionism, and extravagant love of elegance, which, along with fear, is perhaps the dominant motive in their life. The constantly recur- ring struggle of Rangda and Barong to an inevitable draw is thus—for the believing Balinese—both the formulation of a general religious con- ception and the authoritative experience which justifies, even compels, its acceptance. 44 G. Bateson and M. Mead, Balinese Character, p. 36. Religion As a Cultural System 119... that the moods and motivations seem uniquely realistic But no one, not even a saint, lives in the world religious symbols for- mulate all of the time, and the majority of men live in it only at mo- ments. The everyday world of common-sense objects and practical acts is, as Schutz says, the paramount reality in human experience— paramount in the sense that it is the world in which we are most solidly rooted, whose inherent actuality we can hardly question (however much we may question certain portions of it), and from whose pressures and requirements we can least escape.45 A man, even large groups of men, may be aesthetically insensitive, religiously unconcerned, and un- equipped to pursue formal scientific analysis, but he cannot be com- pletely lacking in common sense and survive. The dispositions which re- ligious rituals induce thus have their most important impact—from a human point of view—outside the boundaries of the ritual itself as they reflect back to color the individual's conception of the established world of bare fact. The peculiar tone that marks the Plains vision quest, the Manus confession, or the Javanese mystical exercise pervades areas of the life of these peoples far beyond the immediately religious, impress- ing upon them a distinctive style in the sense both of a dominant mood and a characteristic movement. The interweaving of the malignant and the comic, which the Rangda-Barong combat depicts, animates a very wide range of everyday Balinese behavior, much of which, like the rit- ual itself, has an air of candid fear narrowly contained by obsessive playfulness. Religion is sociologically interesting not because, as vulgar positivism would have it, it describes the social order (which, in so far as it does, it does not only very obliquely but very incompletely), but because, like environment, political power, wealth, jural obligation, per- sonal affection, and a sense of beauty, it shapes it. The movement back and forth between the religious perspective and the common-sense perspective is actually one of the more obvious em- pirical occurrences on the social scene, though, again, one of the most neglected by social anthropologists, virtually all of whom have seen it happen countless times. Religious belief has usually been presented as a homogeneous characteristic of an individual, like his place of residence, his occupational role, his kinship position, and so on. But religious be- lief in the midst of ritual, where it engulfs the total person, transporting 45 Schutz, The Problem of Social Reality, p. 226ff. 120 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES him, so far as he is concerned, into another mode of existence, and reli- gious belief as the pale, remembered reflection of that experience in the midst of everyday life are not precisely the same thing, and the failure to realize this has led to some confusion, most especially in connection with the so-called primitive-mentality problem. Much of the difficulty between Lévy-Bruhl and Malinowski on the nature of "native thought," for example, arises from a lack of full recognition of this distinction; for where the French philosopher was concerned with the view of real- ity savages adopted when taking a specifically religious perspective, the Polish-English ethnographer was concerned with that which they adopted when taking a strictly common-sense one.46 Both perhaps vaguely sensed that they were not talking about exactly the same thing, but where they went astray was in failing to give a specific accounting of the way in which these two forms of "thought"—or, as I would rather say, these two modes of symbolic formulations—interacted, so that where Lévy-Bruhl's savages tended to live, despite his postludial disclaimers, in a world composed entirely of mystical encounters, Mali- nowski's tended to live, despite his stress on the functional importance of religion, in a world composed entirely of practical actions. They be- came reductionists (an idealist is as much of a reductionist as a materi- alist) in spite of themselves because they failed to see man as moving more or less easily, and very frequently, between radically contrasting ways of looking at the world, ways which are not continuous with one another but separated by cultural gaps across which Kierkegaardian leaps must be made in both directions: There are as many innumerable kinds of different shock experiences as there are different finite provinces of meaning upon which I may bestow the ac- cent of reality. Some instances are: the shock of falling asleep as the leap into the world of dreams; the inner transformation we endure if the curtain in the theatre rises as the transition to the world of the stageplay; the radical change in our attitude if. before a painting, we permit our visual field to be limited by what is within the frame as the passage into the pictorial world; our quandary relaxing into laughter, if. in listening to a joke, we are for a short time ready to accept the fictitious world of the jest as a reality in rela- tion to which the world of our daily life takes on the character of foolish- ness; the child's turning toward his toy as the transition into the play-world; and so on. But also the religious experiences in all their varieties—for in- stance. Kierkegaard's experience of the "instant" as the leap into the reli- gious sphere—are examples of such a shock, as well as the decision of the 46 Malinowski, Magic, Science and Religion; L. Lévy-Bruhl, How Natives Think (New York. 1926). Religion As a Cultural System 121 scientist to replace all passionate participation in the affairs of "this world" by a disinterested [analytical] altitude.47 The recognition and exploration of the qualitative difference—an empirical, not a transcendental difference—between religion pure and religion applied, between an encounter with the supposedly "really real" and a viewing of ordinary experience in light of what that encounter seems to reveal, will, therefore, take us further toward an understanding of what a Bororo means when he says "I am a parakeet," or a Christian when he says "1 am a sinner," than either a theory of primitive mysti- cism in which the commonplace world disappears into a cloud of cu- rious ideas or of a primitive pragmatism in which religion disintegrates into a collection of useful fictions. The parakeet example, which I take from Percy, is a good one.48 For, as he points out, it is unsatisfactory to say either that the Bororo thinks he is literally a parakeet (for he does not try to mate with other parakeets), that his statement is false or non- sense (for, clearly, he is not offering—or at least not only offering— the sort of class-membership argument which can be confirmed or re- futed as, say, "1 am a Bororo" can be confirmed or refuted), or yet again that it is false scientifically but true mythically (because that leads immediately to the pragmatic fiction notion which, as it denies the acco- lade of truth to "myth" in the very act of bestowing it, is internally self-contradictory). More coherently it would seem to be necessary to see the sentence as having a different sense in the context of the "finite province of meaning" which makes up the religious perspective and of that which makes up the common-sensical. In the religious, our Bororo is "really" a "parakeet," and given the proper ritual context might well "mate" with other "parakeets"—with metaphysical ones like himself, not commonplace ones such as those which fly bodily about in ordinary trees. In the common-sensical perspective he is a parakeet in the sense —I assume—that he belongs to a clan whose members regard the par- akeet as their totem, a membership from which, given the fundamental nature of reality as the religious perspective reveals it, certain moral and practical consequences flow. A man who says he is a parakeet is, if he says it in normal conversation, saying that, as myth and ritual dem- onstrate, he is shot through with parakeetness and that this religious fact has some crucial social implications—we parakeets must stick to- 47 Schutz, The Problem of Social Reality, p. 231. 48 W. Percy, "The Symbolic Structure of Interpersonal Process," Psychiatry 24 (1961): 39-52. 122 THE INTERPRETATION OF CULTURES gether, not marry one another, not eat mundane parakeets, and so on, for to do otherwise is to act against the grain of the whole universe. It is this placing of proximate acts in ultimate contexts that makes reli- gion, frequently at least, socially so powerful. It alters, often radically, the whole landscape presented to common sense, alters it in such a way that the moods and motivations induced by religious practice seem themselves supremely practical, the only sensible ones to adopt given the way things "really" are. Having ritually "lept" (the image is perhaps a bit too athletic for the actual facts—"slipped" might be more accurate) into the framework of meaning which religious conceptions define, and the ritual ended, re- turned again to the common-sense world, a man is—unle