Document Details

Uploaded by Deleted User

Tags

meta-ethics moral philosophy ethical theory philosophy

Summary

These notes provide an overview of meta-ethics, exploring different perspectives on the nature of goodness. The topic covers various theories like ethical naturalism, non-naturalism, and different views on the nature and meaning of ethical language. Key concepts and figures in meta-ethics, such as Hume, Ayer, and Mackie, are discussed.

Full Transcript

‭Introduction‬ ‭“There is nothing either good or bad, but thinking makes it so”‬‭– William‬ ‭Shakespeare’s ‘Hamlet’.‬ ‭ his topic is about whether right and wrong are real or just a matter of‬ T ‭opinion/feeling. Perhaps what we think is right/wrong is merely the result...

‭Introduction‬ ‭“There is nothing either good or bad, but thinking makes it so”‬‭– William‬ ‭Shakespeare’s ‘Hamlet’.‬ ‭ his topic is about whether right and wrong are real or just a matter of‬ T ‭opinion/feeling. Perhaps what we think is right/wrong is merely the result of‬ ‭our upbringing. How do we know we were raised in the right culture? Does‬ ‭there actually have to be a‬‭right‬‭culture? What would‬‭that even‬‭mean?‬ ‭ eta-ethics is the area of philosophy which attempts to answer the‬ M ‭question of what goodness actually is, including whether it even exists.‬ ‭ ormative ethical theories attempt to devise a system for determining‬ N ‭which actions are good and which are bad, e.g., Utilitarianism, Kantian‬ ‭deontology and Virtue ethics.‬ ‭ ormative ethical theories all have a Meta-ethical core. Some forms of‬ N ‭utilitarianism claim that goodness = pleasure/happiness. That is a‬ ‭meta-ethical view about what goodness is which forms Utilitarianism’s‬ ‭meta-ethical core. Once that is established, Utilitarianism can go on to‬ ‭formulate the details of a system that enables us determine which actions‬ ‭are good and which bad. For example, in the case of Act Utilitarianism, that‬ ‭would include the hedonic calculus.‬ ‭ ormative theories‬‭typically‬‭require that goodness‬‭at least exists, though‬ N ‭they argue over what it actually is. However, some meta-ethical theories‬ ‭(anti-realist theories) claim that goodness does not actually exist. This‬ ‭makes the outcome of meta-ethical debate is crucial for normative ethics. If‬ ‭there is no such thing as objective goodness/badness then it seems difficult‬ ‭to construct a normative theory. If goodness does exist, then what exactly‬ ‭goodness is will limit normative theories to whatever goodness is.‬ ‭ here are‬‭two‬‭main aspects to the question of what‬‭goodness is:‬ T ‭metaphysical and linguistic.‬ ‭ etaphysical‬‭: What is the nature of goodness? There are two opposing‬ M ‭views on this:‬ ‭‬ M ‭ oral Realism:‬‭The view that moral properties (like‬ ‭goodness/badness) exist in reality.‬ ‭‬ ‭Moral anti-realism:‬‭The view that moral properties‬‭(like‬ ‭goodness/badness) do not exist in reality.‬ ‭ inguistic‬‭: What is the meaning of ethical language?‬‭There are two‬ L ‭opposing views on this:‬ ‭‬ C ‭ ognitivism:‬‭ethical language expresses beliefs about‬‭reality‬ ‭which can therefore be true or false.‬ ‭‬ ‭Non-cognitivism:‬‭ethical language expresses some‬ ‭non-cognition like an emotion, does not attempt to describe reality‬ ‭and therefore cannot be true or false.‬ ‭Ethical Naturalism (cognitivist realism)‬ ‭ thical naturalism is the view that goodness is something real in the natural‬ E ‭(physical) world – typically a natural‬‭property‬‭. A‬‭natural property is a trait or‬ ‭feature of natural things.‬ ‭ his makes naturalism is cognitive. Ethical language expresses beliefs‬ T ‭related to the natural property of goodness.‬ ‭ ristotelian naturalism.‬‭Aristotle claims that goodness‬‭= eudaimonia‬ A ‭(flourishing). Flourishing is a factual feature of natural organisms. Philippa‬ ‭Foot defends this view, pointing to the example of plants. There is a factual,‬ ‭natural difference between a plant that is flourishing and a plant that is not.‬ ‭The same is true for humans.‬ ‭ tilitarian naturalism‬‭. Bentham claims that goodness‬‭= pleasure.‬ U ‭Pleasure is a natural property of natural creatures (at least if you don’t‬ ‭believe in a non-natural soul).‬ ‭ he linguistic claims of naturalism.‬‭Naturalism is cognitive. It claims‬ T ‭moral properties like goodness are natural properties.‬ ‭Naturalism vs Hume’s ‘is-ought’ gap‬ ‭A strength of Naturalism‬‭is Aristotle, Bentham and‬‭Mill’s arguments for it.‬ ‭ ristotle’s argument was that eudaimonia (flourishing) is our telos. Every‬ A ‭human action is naturally aimed at living a good life, so that must be our‬ ‭purpose.‬ ‭ he classical Utilitarians adapted this argument, removing telos which had‬ T ‭come to be seen as an unscientific concept and replacing flourishing with‬ ‭pleasure (Bentham) or happiness (Mill).‬ “‭ Nature has placed us under the governance of two sovereign masters,‬ ‭pain and pleasure. It is for them alone to point out what we ought to do, as‬ ‭well as to determine what we shall do … a man may pretend to abjure their‬ ‭empire: but in reality he will remain subject to it all the while”.‬‭– Bentham.‬ I‭t is part of our nature to seek pleasure and avoid pain, so that inescapably‬ ‭determines our morality.‬ ‭ ill builds on this, using the broader term ‘happiness’. Happiness is our‬ M ‭ultimate end. Everything else is valued only insofar as it brings happiness.‬ ‭ entham and Mill try to capture the psychological essence of the‬ B ‭experience of pleasure. It does seem intrinsic to the experience of‬ ‭pleasure/happiness that it is good.‬ ‭Weakness: Hume’s is-ought gap‬ ‭ ume’s is-ought gap attempts to show that moral judgments cannot be‬ H ‭inferred‬‭from facts.‬ ‭ ume’s is-ought gap (also called Hume’s law) criticises naturalism and‬ H ‭cognitivism. Hume said philosophers talk about the way things are and then‬ j‭ump with no apparent justification to a claim about the way things ought to‬ ‭be. Put another way, you cannot deduce a value from a fact. You can’t get‬ ‭an ought from an is.‬ ‭Applying this to Bentham’s argument:‬ ‭ 1. It is human nature to find pleasure good (fact – ‘is-statement’).‬ P ‭C1. Pleasure is good and we ought to maximise pleasure (value – ‘ought’‬ ‭statement)‬ ‭ ume’s point is that this is not a valid deduction. This conclusion does not‬ H ‭follow, is not justified, by that premise. The fact that it is human nature to‬ ‭find pleasure good,‬‭only means that it is human nature‬‭to find pleasure‬ ‭good.‬‭It doesn’t mean that pleasure‬‭is‬‭good and that‬‭we‬‭ought‬‭to‬ ‭maximise pleasure.‬ ‭ on-cognitivism.‬‭Since our moral judgements could‬‭not have been‬ N ‭inferred from facts, they must have a different origin. Hume proposes that‬ ‭ethical language comes from ‘the heart’, not ‘the understanding’. It‬ ‭expresses an ‘active feeling or sentiment’. This makes the is-ought gap‬ ‭also an argument against cognitivism and for non-cognitivism. Hume is‬ ‭arguably a proto-emotivist.‬ ‭ oral judgements can’t be deduced from facts, they are instead‬‭caused‬‭by‬ M ‭non-cognitive personal feelings.‬ ‭Evaluation defending Naturalist realism & cognitivism‬ ‭ atricia Churchland proposes that Hume’s argument only targets deductive‬ P ‭reasoning from is to ought.‬ ‭ e could take Bentham and Mill’s arguments for utilitarian naturalism as‬ W ‭inductive.‬ ‭ ill especially seems to accept that he is making an inductive argument‬ M ‭when he admits that his proof of Utilitarianism is the ‘only proof’ possible.‬ ‭ leasure being our natural end doesn’t deductively‬‭entail/mean‬‭pleasure is‬ P ‭good, but it is inductive‬‭evidence‬‭for pleasure being good. So, Hume’s‬ ‭critique doesn’t apply.‬ ‭ he utilitarian naturalist claim that goodness = pleasure/happiness is not‬ T ‭based on mere baseless assumption, then. It is based on evidence.‬ ‭Evaluation criticising Naturalist realism & cognitivism‬ ‭ urthermore,‬‭consider that we have strong evidence‬‭that human nature‬ F ‭finding pleasure good is the result of evolution, in order to guide animals to‬ ‭evolutionary goals. So, we are not justified in regarding our nature finding‬ ‭pleasure good as evidence for pleasure actually being good since we have‬ ‭stronger evidence for it being the result of something else (evolution).‬ ‭ oore’s non-naturalist Intuitionism‬ M ‭(cognitivist realism)‬ ‭ oore developed Hume’s criticisms of naturalism. However, once he‬ M ‭thought he had shown naturalism to be false, he did not abandon objective‬ ‭morality like Hume did. Moore thought there was another way for goodness‬ ‭to be real than as a natural property.‬ ‭Moore’s open question argument‬ ‭ oore argued that if naturalism were true, the result would be illogical.‬ M ‭Take any naturalist claim about what goodness is, such as that goodness =‬ ‭pleasure.‬ I‭F: goodness = pleasure‬ ‭THEN: (goodness = pleasure) = (pleasure = pleasure).‬ ‭BUT: goodness = pleasure is informative, telling us about the world.‬ ‭YET: pleasure = pleasure is not informative (tautology).‬ ‭ n informative statement cannot be equal in meaning to an uninformative‬ A ‭tautological statement. So, goodness cannot = pleasure, or any other‬ ‭natural property. Therefore, naturalism is false.‬ ‭ question is closed if it shows ignorance of the meanings of the terms‬ A ‭involved to ask. A question is open if it does not display ignorance of those‬ ‭meanings to ask it. Since ‘Goodness = X natural property’ for a naturalist‬ ‭would be synthetic, one could be acquainted with the subject (goodness)‬ ‭but not the predicate (X natural property) and therefore would not‬ ‭necessarily be displaying ignorance of the terms involved to ask the‬ ‭question. Therefore, it will always be an open question whether goodness‬ ‭really is X natural property as we can always meaningfully and intelligibly‬ ‭ask the question ‘is goodness really X natural property?’‬ ‭Moore’s naturalistic fallacy‬ ‭ oore developed Hume’s is-ought gap into the naturalistic fallacy: It is a‬ M ‭fallacy to assume that something being natural means that it is good.‬ ‭ aturalists seem to make that assumption. Bentham assumes that it being‬ N ‭natural to ultimately desire pleasure means pleasure is good. This commits‬ ‭the naturalistic fallacy.‬ ‭ oore intended the naturalistic fallacy to attack other forms of‬ M ‭non-naturalism too. E.g. divine command theory claims that goodness =‬ ‭being commanded by God. But if God commands something, that only‬ ‭means that God commands something. It doesn’t mean that it is Good.‬ ‭What‬‭makes‬‭God’s commands good?‬ ‭ hatever way goodness is proposed to be defined, whether natural things‬ W ‭like pleasure or non-natural things like the commands of a God, it seems‬ ‭impossible to actually have a reason for doing so. All definitions of‬ ‭goodness therefore rest on baseless assumption and so commit the‬ ‭naturalistic fallacy.‬ ‭ oore concluded that we can’t define goodness. We can’t say what‬ M ‭goodness is because it is only itself – it is‬‭sui‬‭generis‬‭(unique). This‬ ‭ xplains why goodness cannot be equated in terms of anything else, as‬ e ‭shown by the naturalistic fallacy and open question arguments.‬ ‭ oodness is like the color yellow. You can’t describe or define yellow, you‬ G ‭just know it intuitively when you apprehend it. Similarly, we just know‬ ‭whether an action is good or bad through intuition, i.e., we know it without‬ ‭figuring it out through a process of reasoning.‬ ‭Moore’s Non-naturalism‬ ‭ his makes Moore a non-naturalist, the view that goodness is a non-natural‬ T ‭property. This goes back to Plato’s theory of forms & the form of the good,‬ ‭which is not a natural thing. Moore didn’t believe in the world of forms, but‬ ‭he did think goodness was real and yet not natural. He drew an analogy.‬ ‭Numbers are real in some way, but they are clearly not natural physical‬ ‭objects. So, there must be more to reality than just the natural. Goodness is‬ ‭real in a similar non-natural form. So, the failure of naturalism is not the end‬ ‭of moral realism.‬ ‭Moore’s Intuitionism‬ I‭ntuitionism is the theory that we know what is good/bad right/wrong‬ ‭through intuition, without any process of reasoning.‬ ‭ strength of intuitionist cognitivism is that it fits with human psychology.‬ A ‭Moore argues that when we observe or reflect on a moral action and its‬ ‭consequences, we intuitively know whether it was right or wrong.‬ ‭. E. Moore’s meta-ethics is non-naturalist intuitionism. It is a cognitivist‬ G ‭theory, claiming ethical language expresses belief about the objective‬ ‭rightness or wrongness of an action.‬ ‭Intuitionism & moral dis/agreement‬ ‭Strength of Moore’s intuitionism: cross-cultural moral agreement‬ ‭ here are a set of core moral principles similar in all societies however,‬ T ‭such as prohibitions on stealing and murder. This shows there is some‬ ‭absolutist moral truth that all humans are somehow apprehending.‬ ‭ hile there is also moral disagreement, Moore argues this is due to people‬ W ‭not articulating their moral views clearly. Pritchard further added that‬ ‭disagreement is caused by people having different levels of practical‬ ‭knowledge about the world and levels of personal moral development.‬ ‭Weakness: Mackie’s argument from relativity‬ ‭ ackie attacks moral realism with an‬‭abductive‬‭argument.‬‭He notes that‬ M ‭there is cross-cultural moral disagreement. This does not prove that there‬ ‭are no objective moral properties, no more than people disagreeing about‬ ‭the shape of the earth proves there is no objective shape of the earth.‬ ‭ owever, consider the‬‭reasons‬‭for moral disagreement‬‭verses scientific‬ H ‭disagreement. The reason for scientific disagreements is access to‬ ‭evidence and ability to make intelligent hypotheses. Mackie argues the‬ ‭reason for moral disagreement is best explained by adherence to different‬ ‭forms of life, i.e., social conditioning.‬ ‭ ackie accepts that of course he can’t‬‭prove‬‭that‬‭there isn’t some‬ M ‭mysterious non-natural moral property influences our moral views.‬ ‭However, his point is‬‭we have no reason to think there‬‭is,‬‭especially‬ ‭when we have the‬‭better explanation‬‭for our moral‬‭views of social‬ ‭conditioning. Intuitionists can attempt to explain moral disagreement in‬ ‭ways that fit their theory, but that does not overcome Mackie’s criticism.‬ ‭Relativism and conditioning is simply a better explanation of moral‬ ‭disagreement than Intuitionism.‬ ‭ eople have moral intuitions, but they are better explained by social‬ P ‭conditioning than intuition of non-natural properties.‬ ‭Evaluation criticising Intuitionism‬ ‭ urthermore, we could explain the moral agreement through evolution and‬ F ‭the universal practical requirements for a society to exist. So, a core set of‬ ‭ ross-cultural moral views exist because of practical necessity, not because‬ c ‭of absolutist objective moral truths.‬ ‭ ume’s non-cognitive moral‬ H ‭psychology (theory of motivation)‬ ‭ n argument supporting non-cognitivism against cognitivism is Hume’s‬ A ‭theory of motivation. It aims to show that moral judgements (i.e., thinking “X‬ ‭is right/wrong”) cannot be‬‭caused‬‭by reason.‬ ‭ oral judgements involve motivation to action. Motivation must involve‬ M ‭desire (mental sates which attract or repel our behaviour).‬ ‭ oral judgements always come after and are joined with emotional‬ M ‭approval or disapproval. We have positive or negative emotion towards an‬ ‭action and then judge it good or bad.‬ ‭ eason does not have control over emotions, so it cannot create moral‬ R ‭judgements. In fact, Hume claimed it was the other way around, that‬ ‭reason is‬‭“the slave of the passions”.‬‭Reason can‬‭only create beliefs about‬ ‭how to satisfy/achieve our desired ends.‬ ‭ e have particular emotional associations and feelings due to our socially‬ W ‭conditioned preferences and biases. Reason then provides‬‭ad hoc‬ ‭rationalisations for our prejudices. Our mind is more like a lawyer than a‬ ‭scientist.‬ ‭ o, desire is the foundational motivator of moral judgements, not reason.‬ S ‭Ethical language thus expresses non-cognitive desires.‬ ‭“Reason alone can never be a motive to any action of the will”‬‭– Hume.‬ “‭ Morals excite passions, and produce or prevent actions. Reason of itself is‬ ‭utterly impotent in this particular. The rules of morality, therefore, are not‬ ‭conclusions of reason”‬‭– Hume.‬ ‭ 1. Moral judgements are motivating.‬ P ‭P2. Reason & belief are not motivating.‬ ‭C1. Reason cannot create moral judgements.‬ ‭C2. Moral judgements express non-cognitive states.‬ ‭ eakness of non-cognitivism & strength of cognitivism: Aristotelian‬ W ‭virtue ethics‬ ‭ sychologist Jonathan Haidt creates an illustration to show how Hume‬ P ‭went too far calling reason a ‘slave’. Emotions are like an elephant and‬ ‭reason is like its rider. The elephant will‬‭often‬‭just go wherever it likes,‬ ‭dragging the rider along with it. Nonetheless, over the long-term, the rider‬ ‭can control the general direction of the elephant. Similarly, a human’s‬ ‭reason can control their general behaviour despite their emotions, e.g.‬ ‭getting themselves to revise by planning rewards and rest breaks.‬ ‭ aidt’s point resonates with the insights of Aristotelian virtue ethics. Hume‬ H ‭was right that our emotions‬‭affect‬‭reason and our‬‭moral judgements.‬ ‭Aristotle also accepted that our emotions are not under the direct control of‬ ‭reason. Reason does have‬‭indirect‬‭control, however.‬‭Over the long-term‬ ‭we can cultivate habits which control our emotions.‬ ‭ hen a person says “X is wrong”, they are partly expressing how they feel,‬ W ‭and they feel that way partly due to social conditioning. However, Hume‬ ‭was wrong to leave his analysis there. People also have a degree of‬ ‭rational autonomy. We can rationally control and cultivate our emotional‬ ‭reactions and habits towards flourishing. Then, our moral judgements also‬ ‭expresses cognitions regarding flourishing or what a virtuous person would‬ ‭do.‬ ‭Evaluation defending non-cognitivism‬ ‭ aidt and virtue ethicists’ critique of Hume is unsuccessful because it fails‬ H ‭to consider that our rational cultivation of our emotional reactions could‬ ‭itself be driven by desire.‬ ‭ ume could accept that reason can sometimes cultivate a control over our‬ H ‭emotions.‬ ‭ owever, we can still question‬‭why‬‭reason chose to cultivate the emotional‬ H ‭habits it did.‬ ‭ he ultimate root must still be desire. During cultivation of virtue, we desire‬ T ‭to control our desires.‬ ‭ he foundational root of all human behaviour is still desire and therefore‬ T ‭the fundamental states being expressed through ethical language are‬ ‭non-cognitions.‬ ‭Evaluation defending cognitivism‬ ‭ he virtue ethics critique of Hume is successful because in virtuous people,‬ T ‭beliefs could cause desires which then motivate action.‬ ‭ irtue ethicist McDowell develops this point using virtue ethics. Beliefs‬ V ‭cause desires which then motivate action depending on the moral outlook‬ ‭and general understanding of how to live (virtue) of the person in question,‬ ‭which explains why the same belief causes a desire in some, (virtuous‬ ‭people) but not others (because they lack virtue).‬ ‭Emotivism‬ ‭Ayer’s Emotivism‬ ‭ ume concluded, and Ayer agreed, that moral judgements are not‬ H ‭judgements of reason. The origin of our moral judgements is our feelings.‬ ‭When we call something good or bad, we are expressing how we‬ ‭personally feel about it. We express non-cognitions, like emotional approval‬ ‭or disapproval.‬ ‭ oore accepted that Hume countered naturalism, but attempted to suggest‬ M ‭that ‘goodness’ could still be a non-natural property. Ayer rejects that as‬ ‭unverifiable and thus meaningless.‬ ‭ yer also accepted the fact-value distinction implied by Hume’s theory of‬ A ‭motivation and is-ought gap.‬ ‭ yer thinks we are therefore left with anti-realism. We cannot assert that‬ A ‭there are either natural nor non-natural moral properties. So, anti-realism is‬ ‭true. Ethical language expresses emotion, so non-cognitivism is true.‬ ‭ he boo/hurrah theory.‬‭Saying ‘X is wrong’ is just‬‭saying ‘boo to X’, or just‬ T ‭saying X with a really disgusted tone of voice. When we call things good or‬ ‭bad, right or wrong, we are just having an emotional outburst. Saying ‘X is‬ ‭good’ is just saying ‘hurrah to X’.‬ ‭ his fits with the reality of human psychology. When people engage in‬ T ‭moral debates, it does seem that they are merely having an emotional‬ ‭conflict. That’s why moral debates are often described as ‘heated’.‬ ‭Hume’s fork & Ayer’s verificationism‬ ‭ n important pillar of Ayer’s anti-realism and emotivist‬ A ‭non-cognitivism is Hume’s fork and its development into the‬ ‭verification principle.‬ ‭ ume’s fork aims to show that moral judgements cannot be judgements of‬ H ‭reason (neither analytic or synthetic).‬ ‭Hume’s fork claims that there are two types of judgements of reason:‬ ‭.‬ ‭Synthetic judgements, only known a posteriori.‬ 1 ‭2.‬ ‭Analytic judgements, only known a priori.‬ ‭ yer’s verification principle‬‭expanded this to become‬‭the criteria of‬ A ‭meaningful cognitive language. A statement is only meaningful if it is either‬ ‭analytic or empirically verifiable through experience.‬ ‭ irstly, ethical statements are not analytic. Analytic statements are true by‬ F ‭definition and cannot be denied without contradiction. Denying that ‘a‬ ‭Batchelor is an unmarried man’ is contradictory. Ethical statements can be‬ ‭denied without contradiction. If I deny that ‘stealing is wrong’, there is no‬ ‭apparent contradiction. The concept of ‘stealing’ does not seem‬ ‭contradicted by ‘not wrong’.‬ ‭ econdly, ethical statements are not synthetic nor empirically verifiable.‬ S ‭Moral properties like ‘goodness’ and ‘badness’ do not seem to exist in‬ ‭experience. They are not observable. In a supposedly ‘moral’ action, we‬ ‭could list the physical facts about it which we can experience. The so-called‬ ‭‘good/badness’ of the action cannot be found amongst them.‬ ‭ o, moral judgements are neither analytic nor synthetic (Hume), nor‬ S ‭empirically verifiable (Ayer).‬ ‭Counter:‬ ‭ either Hume’s fork nor the verification principle themselves seem analytic‬ N ‭as they can be denied without contradiction, but it’s hard to see how either‬ ‭could be inferred from experience. So, they fail their own test. Hume’s fork‬ ‭is not a judgement of reason. The verification principle is meaningless.‬ ‭ owever, it is important to note that Ayer did not think his emotivism really‬ H ‭needed verificationism. He thought that even if verificationism were proven‬ ‭false, he could still rely on Hume’s motivation argument for non-cognitivism‬ ‭to show that ethical language expressed emotions.‬ ‭Mackie’s anti-realist arguments‬ ‭ ackie’s anti-realist arguments are in a stronger position than Hume and‬ M ‭Ayer’s because they do not rely on empiricist doctrines like the fork or‬ ‭verification principle.‬ ‭ ackie thinks that the linguistic approach to meta-ethics was flawed. Ayer’s‬ M ‭verification principle and also Moore’s open question argument &‬ ‭naturalistic fallacy were overly focused on linguistic analysis of moral‬ ‭concepts. They wrongly thought linguistic analysis entitled them to draw‬ ‭metaphysical conclusions.‬ “‭ There are questions of factual rather than conceptual analysis: the‬ ‭problem of what goodness is cannot be settled conclusively or exhaustively‬ ‭by finding out what the word ‘good’ means, or what it is conventionally used‬ t‭o say or to do. Recent philosophy, biased as it has been towards various‬ ‭kinds of linguistic inquiry, has tended to doubt this.” –‬‭Mackie.‬ ‭ ackie instead makes the argument that objective values are actually‬ M ‭‘queer’ and thus incomprehensible.‬ ‭ etaphysical queerness.‬‭As Hume pointed out, there‬‭is a connection‬ M ‭between moral judgments and motivation. If moral realism were true and‬ ‭moral judgements were somehow reflective of reality, there would have to‬ ‭be objective moral properties which motivate us. Mackie sums this up as‬ ‭that ‘not-to-be-doneness’ would be somehow present in reality. It’s‬ ‭impossible to conceive of what that would involve. This is grounds for‬ ‭thinking there are no objective moral properties.‬ ‭ pistemological queerness.‬‭Even if there were objective‬‭moral‬ E ‭properties, how could we know them? Moore’s answer that we just have a‬ ‭mysterious faculty of intuition is arguably not an answer because it doesn’t‬ ‭explain how that faculty works.‬ ‭Evaluation defending moral realism‬ ‭ ackie’s queerness arguments really only work against non-naturalism, not‬ M ‭naturalism.‬ I‭f we could prove that goodness is pleasure or flourishing, then there would‬ ‭be nothing incomprehensible about moral properties existing, motivating us‬ ‭nor how we come to have knowledge of them. It’s not strange at all that we‬ ‭would be motivated to flourish.‬ ‭ ackie’s relativity argument claimed social conditioning was the best‬ M ‭explanation of our moral views. Virtue ethicists again can respond that‬ ‭while this is often true, humans can cultivate virtues and rational autonomy‬ ‭to indirectly control their emotional reactions. So, we are not solely led by‬ ‭social conditioning or adherence to a form of life. Our moral views can‬ ‭sometimes result from rationally cultivated virtuous habits.‬ ‭Utilitarians can respond similarly regarding pleasure/happiness.‬ ‭ he Virtue ethicist defence of‬ T ‭naturalism and critique of Kant & Mill’s‬ ‭response to Hume‬ ‭ cIntyre points out that in ancient times ethics like Aristotle’s grew‬ M ‭organically out of reasoning about the human ends/needs for flourishing‬ ‭inherent to a particular ‘practice’; a form of social/cultural life.‬ ‭. Stocker argues that modernity’s transition from community-life to city-life‬ M ‭required the development of a more impersonal, legalistic and bureaucratic‬ ‭form morality. McIntyre argues modernity separated morality from its‬ ‭foundation in ‘practice’ and reasoning about ends.‬ ‭ his was a mistake because without its foundation in practice, morality‬ T ‭seemed arbitrary and without basis in reality. Hume’s anti-realist arguments‬ ‭then appeared to show moral judgements were separate from reasoning‬ ‭about ends and without a foundation in reason or reality. Hume concluded‬ ‭they merely reflected our socially conditioned emotional associations.‬ ‭ cIntyre argues that Kant, Bentham and Mill responded to Hume in the‬ M ‭wrong way, by trying to find a philosophical foundation for moral goodness‬ ‭by itself, instead of just rejecting the separation of it from practice. Their‬ ‭failure led to modern moral thought being taken over by emotivism.‬ ‭ ant agreed that reasoning about ends is not morality but mere‬ K ‭hypothetical imperatives. Moral rightness is indeed separate like Hume‬ ‭said, but Kant argued it actually could be discovered by reason as the‬ ‭categorical imperative. Bentham and Mill were less accepting of Hume’s‬ ‭separation as they attempted to define goodness as a natural property, but‬ ‭their definition still separated morality from practice.‬ I‭t’s extremely philosophically difficult to find a basis for morality once‬ ‭isolated from practice. A. J. Ayer thought Kant and Mill had failed to‬ ‭overcome Hume’s destruction of objective morality.‬ ‭ he solution proposed by modern virtue ethics revivalists is to return to an‬ T ‭Aristotelian understanding of moral concepts. Anscombe argues that‬ ‭“Ought” really functions like the word “need”, such as a machine needs oil‬ ‭in order to run well. For life in general, ‘ought’ is simply ‘the needs of‬ ‭flourishing’. Humans need certain things in order to flourish, to live well.‬ ‭ hilippa Foot concludes there is “no difficulty” in deriving ought from is.‬ P ‭Foot’s example: it is a fact that children cannot flourish without help from‬ ‭adults, from which we can derive that adults ‘ought’ to protect children.‬ ‭ ume and the modern moral thought he influenced want to press the‬ H ‭meta-ethical response of‬‭why‬‭should one‬‭flourish,‬‭or‬‭why‬‭is flourishing‬ ‭‘good’? Hume, Ayer and Moore think that question cannot be answered‬ ‭meaningfully.‬ ‭ owever, asking that question is confused. To be a living being is to have a‬ H ‭certain function which comes with needs and the potential to flourish if they‬ ‭are met. Nietzsche said that if one doesn’t want to flourish, that’s probably‬ ‭simply a sign that one’s needs are not being met. Asking why flourishing is‬ ‭good is just a sign of not flourishing. There is no extra moral reason for why‬ ‭flourishing is good. Once morality is reabsorbed into human social practice,‬ ‭it no longer looks like a baseless matter of opinion or feeling.‬ ‭ he idea that there needs be some further meta-ethical warrant for morality‬ T ‭is the confusion of modernity. Anscombe and Nietzsche argued this‬ ‭impulse of philosophers is a result of the remaining religious influence on‬ ‭our ethical concepts. We want to find an ultimate source of moral‬ ‭justification, like God. Kant and Mill tried to answer that want. They failed to‬ ‭realise that this question or impulse instead required dissolving through‬ ‭sociological analysis of the conditions that led to it.‬ ‭ ognitive/non-cognitive debate over‬ C ‭how ethical language is used‬ ‭ oore: Cognitivism can account for the way ethical language is used‬ M ‭better than non-cognitivism‬ ‭ oore points out that ethical language appears to involve features like‬ M ‭moral reasoning, persuading and disagreeing. These seem to require‬ ‭cognitions. Disagreement requires contrasting truth claims about reality.‬ ‭Non-cognitive states like emotions can conflict, but they cannot ‘disagree’‬ ‭because they do not represent reality.‬ ‭ eople engage in disputes which are ordinarily thought of as disputes‬ P ‭about value and have what can sound like rational arguments on either‬ ‭side of what seems like a debate. If ethical language were really just an‬ ‭expression of emotion, that should not be possible.‬ ‭ 1. Disagreement requires contrasting beliefs about reality.‬ P ‭P2. Non-cognitive states like emotions cannot disagree.‬ ‭P3. Ethical language involves moral disagreement.‬ ‭C2. Ethical language is cognitive.‬ ‭Prescriptivism (anti-realist & non-cognitivist)‬ ‭. M. Hare invented prescriptivism. He intended it to be an improvement on‬ R ‭emotivism. Hare agreed with Ayer that Hume had successfully shown that‬ ‭anti-realism was true. Hare also agreed that non-cognitivism was true.‬ ‭However, Hare was not satisfied with Ayer’s reduction of ethical language‬ ‭completely to emotion. Hare thought that ethical language did indeed‬ ‭express emotion – but also and primarily expressed prescriptions.‬ ‭Prescriptions are like commands or recommendation. For Hare, if someone‬ ‭says ‘stealing is wrong’ that just means ‘don’t steal’. This is still‬ ‭non-cognitive because the statement can’t be true or false.‬ ‭ are was influenced by Kant. Kant thought that actions are only morally‬ H ‭good if they are universalizable – i.e., if everyone can do them. Hare‬ ‭doesn’t think there is such a thing as good or bad – but he did think Kant‬ ‭was partially right about how ethical language functions. When we say‬ ‭‘stealing is wrong’ we are intending to universally prescribe that action to‬ ‭everyone. When I say ‘stealing is wrong’, that means ‘don’t steal’ and it‬ ‭means that I’m prescribing that no one should steal.‬ ‭ are’s solution to moral disagreement.‬‭Hare thought‬‭his approach‬ H ‭helped to explain the role of reason, logic and disagreement in ethical‬ l‭anguage, which seem irreducible to emotion. When we make a‬ ‭prescription, however, we do need to use reason and logic to think about‬ ‭whether we would really accept it universally in all cases. Prescriptions can‬ ‭conflict with each other, causing what appears to be moral disagreement.‬ ‭ are illustrated with the example of Nazis who thought killing Jews should‬ H ‭be universally prescribed. Imagine a Nazi found out they were Jewish. Most‬ ‭would not want to be killed. But then, they do not really accept their own‬ ‭universal prescription. So, Nazis are irrational. This doesn’t mean they are‬ ‭objectively wrong, but it does explain the role of reason, logic and‬ ‭disagreement in ethical language better than Ayer did.‬ ‭ ackie’s error theory & critique of‬ M ‭non-cognitivism‬ ‭ ackie’s argument for cognitivism.‬‭Mackie is an anti-realist.‬‭However,‬ M ‭he argues people‬‭think‬‭good/bad objectively exists‬‭and so they‬‭talk‬‭about‬ ‭good/bad‬‭as if‬‭they did. This makes ethical language‬‭cognitive, expressing‬ ‭belief about reality. However, the unusual thing about Mackie’s theory is‬ ‭that he combines cognitivism with anti-realism. So, since there are no‬ ‭objective moral properties, all ethical beliefs are false, a position called‬ ‭error theory.‬ ‭Ethical terms like ‘good’:‬ ‘‭are used as if it were the name of a supposed non-natural quality’‬‭–‬ ‭Mackie.‬ I‭f we were to ask a random person of the street whether they thought it was‬ ‭wrong to kill people they would likely say yes. Imagine if we asked if they‬ ‭believed‬‭that was a‬‭fact of reality.‬‭Mackie thinks‬‭they would likely say yes.‬ ‭He concludes that objectivism about values has‬‭‘a‬‭firm basis’‬‭in ordinary‬ ‭thought.‬ ‭ ackie’s argument against the non-cognitivism of Hume, Ayer & Hare.‬ M ‭Mackie accepts that emotivism is ‘part of the truth’ because of Hume’s‬ ‭ sychology. Ethical language expresses non-cognitions that motivate us.‬ p ‭Mackie’s contention is that ethical language‬‭also‬‭expresses cognitions,‬ ‭making it cognitive.‬ ‭ ackie illustrates with a bioweapons research scientist in a state of moral‬ M ‭perplexity, wondering whether their research is morally justifiable.‬ “‭ What they want to decide is not whether they really want to do the work,‬ ‭whether it will satisfy their emotions, whether they will have a positive‬ ‭attitude towards it in the long run, or whether the action is one they can‬ ‭happily, sincerely and rationally recommend or prescribe in all relevantly‬ ‭similar cases.‬‭What they ultimately want to know is‬‭whether this action‬ ‭is ‘wrong in itself’.‬‭”‬‭– Mackie (my emphasis).‬ ‭ hen facing moral dilemmas, we don’t merely seek emotional satisfaction,‬ W ‭nor to know whether a prescription about it is one we could rationally‬ ‭universally recommend. What we want to know is the‬‭objectively right‬ ‭answer about what we‬‭ought/should‬‭do.‬ ‭ ackie concludes that in addition to motivating non-cognitions, ethical‬ M ‭language‬‭also‬‭expresses cognitive beliefs about objective‬‭moral properties.‬ ‘‭ordinary moral judgements include a claim to objectivity, an assumption‬ ‭that there are objective values’-‬‭Mackie.‬ ‭ owever, since Mackie thinks there are no objective moral properties, all‬ H ‭ethical beliefs are false. If someone says “stealing is good”, that’s false‬ ‭because it’s not true that goodness exists. If someone says “stealing is‬ ‭bad”, that’s false because it’s not true that badness exists.‬ ‭ he issue of whether anti-realism‬ T ‭might destroy society (Nihilism)‬ ‭ oral nihilism‬‭is the view that because there is no‬‭right or wrong, morality‬ M ‭is pointless. Anti-realists like Ayer and Hare claim that there are no‬ ‭ bjective moral values. Many object that this view leads to the moral nihilist‬ o ‭conclusion.‬ ‭ he concern arising from moral nihilism is that people might not bother to‬ T ‭be moral. If everyone lost their belief in morality, society might struggle to‬ ‭maintain social order. This criticism gained popularity after world war 2‬ ‭when the details of the holocaust emerged. Foot comments:‬ “‭ in the face of the news of the concentration camps, I thought, ‘It just can’t‬ ‭be the way Stevenson, Ayer, and Hare say it is, that morality is just the‬ ‭expression of an attitude,’ and the subject haunted me.‬ ‭ or, fundamentally, there is no way, if one takes this line, that one could‬ F ‭imagine oneself saying to a Nazi, ‘but we are right, and you are wrong’ with‬ ‭there being any substance to the statement.‬ ‭ orality cannot just be subjective in the way that different attitudes, like‬ M ‭some aesthetic ones, or like and dislikes, are subjective. The separation of‬ ‭descriptions from attitudes, or facts from values, that characterized the‬ ‭current moral philosophy had to be bad philosophy”‬‭– Philippa Foot.‬ ‭Evaluation defending anti-realism‬ ‭ his criticism is a common and natural reaction, but it begs the question.‬ T ‭For leading to moral nihilism to be a criticism of anti-realism, we have to‬ ‭assume that there is something objectively wrong with nihilism. Yet,‬ ‭objective right and wrong is precisely what anti-realism denies. So, the‬ ‭criticism begs the question regarding the truth of moral realism in order to‬ ‭criticise anti-realism.‬ ‭ his criticism arguably fails to even attempt to show anti-realism is actually‬ T ‭false. In a way, it actually proves anti-realism’s point. We perceive actions‬ ‭like the holocaust, and because of our nature and nurture, a negative‬ ‭emotional reaction is caused in us. This then causes us to say that the‬ ‭action was “wrong”. This was Hume’s point all along.‬ ‭ aying we don’t like what it would mean for a theory to be true is not a‬ S ‭philosophical argument against it. Philosophy is about finding out what is‬ t‭rue. If you’d rather not accept what might be true, then stop doing‬ ‭philosophy.‬ ‭Evaluation criticising anti-realism‬ ‭ owever, potentially destroying morality and causing the end of society‬ H ‭doesn’t make Ayer’s theory actually incorrect.‬ ‭ yer would argue Foot viewed the holocaust and had a negative emotional‬ A ‭reaction which she expressed with the word ‘wrong’.‬ ‭ o the nihilism objection alone begs the question regarding the truth of‬ S ‭moral realism, and might ironically simply illustrate Ayer’s emotivism rather‬ ‭than undermine it.‬ ‭ he only way to disprove Ayer – is to prove that morality is actually real.‬ T ‭Foot followed up her presentation of the nihilism issue with the point that‬ ‭the ‘separation’ between facts and values was the foundational mistake.‬ ‭ o Foot presents the nihilism issue in its strongest form. She isn’t saying‬ S ‭the holocaust proves Ayer wrong, just that it is especially illustrative of Ayer‬ ‭and Hume’s foundational mistake of thinking facts and values, or is/oughts‬ ‭were separate.‬ ‭ his defeats all of Hume & Ayer’s anti-realist arguments. If values are a‬ T ‭sort of fact, then they are verifiable a posteriori. So Hume’s fork and Ayer’s‬ ‭verification principle cannot exclude moral judgements. We can verify that‬ ‭the holocaust was disabling of flourishing. That is what Foot did when‬ ‭viewing the footage, she wasn’t merely having an emotional reaction.‬ ‭ o, anti-realism is ultimately false because moral realism is true. Leading to‬ S ‭nihilism doesn’t prove anti-realism false, but it is illustrative of why it’s false;‬ ‭its mistaken separation of facts from values.‬ ‭ he issue of anti-realism accounting‬ T ‭for moral progress‬ ‭ oral progress appears to occur. E.g., society used to accept slavery and‬ M ‭deny women the vote.‬ ‭ he concept of ‘progress’ relies on an objective standard towards which‬ T ‭increasing gains can be made. If moral progress exists, then objective‬ ‭moral values exist. It seems it exists, so it seems objective values exist.‬ ‭Counter:‬ ‭ owever, this criticism begs the question. Anti-realists would deny that‬ H ‭there is an objective moral standard and so they would deny that progress‬ ‭has occurred. Certainly moral‬‭change‬‭has occurred,‬‭but to call it progress‬ ‭begs the question regarding the truth of moral realism.‬ ‭ yer can be defended‬‭with the counter-claim that there‬‭is no such thing as‬ A ‭actual progress. The fact that women can now vote, for example, Ayer‬ ‭would regard as nothing more than that a sufficient number of people were‬ ‭persuaded to have a certain emotional reaction which was what society‬ ‭happened to require for the law to be changed.‬ ‭ are would regard moral progress‬‭as the increasing‬‭rational coherence‬ H ‭of our prescriptions. For example, racism is not universalizable because a‬ ‭racist prescription against another race cannot apply to the speaker or the‬ ‭speakers race. There is ultimately no rational reason to prescribe racism‬ ‭nor to think one’s own race superior to another. Hare would explain the‬ ‭history of moral progress as the gradual erosion of irrational prescriptions‬ ‭and their replacement with rational ones.‬ ‭ ackie acknowledges‬‭that there have been moral reformers‬‭who sought‬ M ‭to instigate moral progress but argues that this does not come from their‬ ‭somehow having figured out objective moral facts. He instead suggests‬ ‭that ‘progress’ in fact resulting from thinking through the already held moral‬ ‭doctrines in a new way or recommending some new action because‬ ‭consistency of it with previous doctrines was desired. For example, the‬ ‭American constitution claims that all men have inalienable rights, and this‬ ‭was used by Martin Luther King to argue that black people should also‬ ‭have equal rights. So, King was merely expanding already existing‬ ‭doctrines not discovering objective moral progress. Mackie thus thinks our‬ ‭ oral views and the changes they undergo originate from what a society‬ m ‭happens to value due to contingencies of history and evolution, not some‬ ‭real objective standard within which their change could count as objective‬ ‭progress.‬

Use Quizgecko on...
Browser
Browser