8th Lesson Politics and the Environment PDF

Summary

This document examines the relationship between the level of democracy and the provision of public goods, specifically focusing on environmental quality. It analyzes the supply and demand sides of this relationship, considering factors such as the size of the winning coalition, political systems (presidential vs. parliamentary), interest groups, and civil liberties. The document also explores the impact of democracy on global environmental policy, using climate change as a case study. The document contains various hypotheses and research designs, including the use of sulfur dioxide (SO2) concentration and CO2 emissions as metrics.

Full Transcript

Politics and the Environment 1 National Institutions and Public Goods Questions 1. Do democracies provide more public goods (better environmental quality) at the domestic level? 2a. Are democracies more cooperative in global environmental policy (out...

Politics and the Environment 1 National Institutions and Public Goods Questions 1. Do democracies provide more public goods (better environmental quality) at the domestic level? 2a. Are democracies more cooperative in global environmental policy (output)? 2b. Do democracies contribute more to the provision of global public goods (outcome): = Focus on climate change, one of the most important global public goods issues facing mankind. 2 Theory: Degree of democracy and public goods Supply side: Positive effect of democracy on public goods provision Reasons: a. Median voter and the provision of public goods Non-democratic regimes are likely to underprovide public goods because they are typically ruled by small elites that use the resources of their respective country to create personal wealth. If the costs of stricter environmental policies are born disproportionately by the elites while the benefits are uniformly dispersed throughout the population, then these elites would have little incentive to implement such policies. Democracies are likely to provide more public goods because the median voter, who decides on public policy, faces lower costs from environmental policies relative to the economic 3 and political elite. b. Institutional arrangements, the selection of leaders and the provision of public goods. : The institutional features of a. the selectorate (i.e., the group of people who can affect the choice of leaders and be the recipients of the benefits distributed by leaders), and b. the winning coalition (i.e., the subgroup of the selectorate maintaining incumbents in office in exchange for special privileges) determine whether governmental policies provide public or private goods. => The argument goes as follows: 4 In autocracies, where the winning coalition is small and the selectorate is large, leaders have to provide the small number of their essential supporters with a relatively large amount of private goods if they wish to remain in power + autocratic institutional structures promote loyalty to the incumbent leader among the privileged few of the winning coalition which further enhances the provision of private goods. In democracies, where the winning coalition is large relative to the selectorate, leaders lack sufficient resources to reward their supporters with high levels of private goods + the weak loyalty norm encourages defection from the incumbent leaders' winning coalition to opposing candidates thus it forces leaders to adopt policies that provide a relatively high level of public goods (such as better environmental quality) to ensure their political survival. => democratic leaders are likely to experience greater incentives (incentives to survive in office) than autocratic counterparts to satisfy public demand for public goods: 5 climate change mitigation Supply side: Negative effect of democracy on public goods provision Reasons a. Myopic behavior In democracies, elected governments may have shorter planning horizons than non-elected governments because of political myopia = Since many forms of environmental degradation develop slowly and over long periods of time (e.g., climate change, biodiversity, air and water pollution), the social costs of current economic behavior and political choices often materialize over the long term and burden future generations and future politicians. => Democracies may, as a result, undersupply environmental public goods relative to non-democratic regimes where political leaders do not face frequent (re-) election and can take, if they want to, more costly decisions (stricter environmental policies) with longer-term benefits without fear 6 of been punished by myopic voters. b. Interest groups = As democratic societies become more advanced and stable, their institutions become more complex and, at some point, stability may turn into rigidity. The influence of special interest groups is in part responsible for institutional sclerosis in mature democracies. in mature democratic systems public goods provision could suffer from the existence of a relatively large number of special interest groups that have little or no incentive to make significant sacrifices in the interest of society as a whole. These groups compete over access to and control over legislative and administrative processes in an attempt to appropriate larger shares of a society’s production = public policy could fall short of improving environmental quality when distributional coalitions, including special interest groups gain the upper hand. 7 Presidential, parliamentary systems and public goods In parliamentary regimes, legislative cohesion that is the disciplined voting by members of a governing coalition, leads to policies aiming at pleasing the majority of voters and consequently increases spending on public goods. In presidential systems, unstable legislative coalitions and the struggle among different minorities over different issues on the legislative agenda lead to inefficiently low spending on public goods. But: According to the selectorate theory, presidential systems, which necessitate a large winning coalition, provide more public goods than parliamentary systems, which require a smaller winning coalition. 8 Demand side: Positive effect of democracy on public goods provision because of civil liberties Civil liberties and the provision of public goods = the existence of civil liberties (freedom of speech, press and association) is likely to make the public in democratic countries more aware of environmental problems and possibilities for their mitigation 9 Hypotheses (environmental outcomes) H1: The larger the winning coalition relative to the selectorate, the lower the SO2 concentration. H2: Presidential democratic systems have lower SO2 concentrations than parliamentary democratic systems. H3.1: The greater the strength of interest groups that tend to lose from more stringent environmental policies, the higher the SO2 concentrations. H3.2: The greater the strength of pro-environmental groups, the lower the SO2 concentrations. H3.3: Civil liberties (a proxy for aggregate interest group influence) have a negative (positive) effect on environmental quality. 10 Research Design Dependent variable: (environmental quality): log of sulfur dioxide (SO2) concentrations (mcg/m3). Annual observations for 1971-1996 from 291 observations sites located in 107 major cities in 42 countries (2555 observations). Source: Global Environment Monitoring System (GEMS) Independent variables: Political: Size of winning coalition relative to selectorate (W/S, varies between 0-1, Bueno de Mesquita et al, 2003) Parliamentary/presidential system (0-1,BDM et al,2003) Labor union strength (Employment protection index, 1-20; Nickell, 1997) Green party shares in national parliaments (Armingeon et al, 2004) 11 Civil liberties (Freedom House, 1-7) Control variables: Wide range of economic and other variables: − scale effect (intensity of economic activity; GDP per square kilometer for each city and each year) − composition effect (capital intensity of production; capital to labor ratio) − technique effect (income; three-year average of lagged GDP per capita) − trade openness (the ratio of the sum of exports and imports to GDP), − topography (central or rural location) − temperature and precipitation − time trend Statistical procedure: Fixed and random effects estimations applied to pooled cross-sectional data 12 13 Results The degree of democracy has a positive effect on environmental quality. Presidential democracies enjoy a better environmental quality than parliamentarian democracies. Labor unions have a negative effect on environmental quality, and green parties a positive effect. Civil liberties do not have any effect beyond that present in the power of labor unions and environmental groups. Thus, these two special interest groups capture adequately any effects that civil liberties may have on the environment. 14 National vs global public goods Even though the complex nature of global problems may weaken the effect of democracy on the provision of public goods still such weakening should be less in democracies than non-democracies. Policy output vs policy outcome Policy output: Democracies are more likely than autocracies to cooperate at the international level, that is, they are more likely to participate in and sign/ratify international environmental regimes. Policy outcome: Democracies, because of reasons such as availability of resources, mitigation costs, efficiency of implemanting agencies, are less able to reduce emissions relative to their willingness to do so. 15 Hypotheses (output and outcome) H1. More democratic countries exhibit stronger political commitment to climate change H2. More democratic countries contribute more to climate change mitigation in terms of emission reduction. However, this positive democracy effect is weaker than the democracy effect on policy output. 16 Research Design Dependent variable: Policy output: composite index (ranging from 0 to 1 with higher values indicating more cooperative behavior) measuring the extent of political, legal, and administrative committments to climate change mitigation, ie a. Whether a coutry has ratified the UN Framework Convention of Climate Change (yes=1/no=0) and how fast it has done so b. Whether a coutry has ratified the Kyoto Protocol (yes=1/no=0) and how fast it has done so c. Whether a country has submitted the latest national climate report (yes=1/no=0) and whether it has done so in time d. How oftern a country has made ist financial contributions to 17 the UNFCCC secretariat in time between 1996 and 2005. Policy outcome: 1. Outcome: index assessing emissions trends (ranging from 0 to 1 with higher values indicating more cooperative behavior) a. 1990 levels of CO2 emissions per capita in relation to GDP per capita. b. The trend of CO2 emissions per capita in relation to GDP per capita between 1990 and 2002 2. Emissslevel: CO2 emissions per capita 3. Emisstrend: growth of CO2 emissions per capita. 18 Independent variable: Democracy: Freedom House political rights index (1 to 7). Control variables: Vulnerability to climate change: Climate Change Index (cci) (0 to 1 scale, higher values indicate higher risk exposure of a country) Income: natural logarithm of GDP per capita and its squared. Trade: trade openness (exports plus imports to GDP) Mitigation costs: CO2 emissions per capita in 1990 Fossil fuel production: total fossil fuel production (oil, coal, gas, in oil equivalent) per capita Statistical procedure: Cross sectional 1990-2005; OLS regression, robust SE, 180+ countries 19 20 Results Net effect of democracy on policy output is positive Net effect of democracy on policy outcomes is not significant Democracy increases green demand, green demand has a positive effect on policy output (but not outcome) Country specific climate risk has no significant effect on climate policy Will democracies perform better in the long-run? (YES) 21 Conclusion Democracies perform better at the political commitment level than in terms of cutting their emissions = “words and deeds” are not strongly related mainly because democracies have hard time in restricting individual freedom and curbing transport related emissions. 22 Appendix I: Theoretical concepts Decision-making mechanisms How do decision-making mechanisms affect which policies are chosen? (Political Economy) But first, How does a society choose the mechanisms for making collective choices (= specific policy decisions)? (Public choice) 23 Appendix I: Theoretical concepts Decision-making mechanisms How do decision-making mechanisms affect which policies are chosen? (Political Economy) But first, How does a society choose the mechanisms for making collective choices (= specific policy decisions)? (Public choice) 24 The creation of a government reflects the payoff of cooperation = it is formed by a voluntary agreement among citizens => governmental decisions should be reached by unanimity vote. However, unanimity is infeasible in large communities because of extremely high (prohibitive) transaction costs (= the costs of trading). Consequently, The choice of rules for making decisions will use a benefit (high payoff to collective action=cooperation) – cost (the infeasibility of unanimity) analysis => simple majority is the smallest possible number of individuals to reach decisions. 25 Condorcet paradox shows how groups differ from the people that comprise them Suppose a group of 3 individuals uses simple majority rule to order 3 alternatives Suppose we feed these 3 complete and transitive preferences into a box. Voter 1 A > B > C (> = preferred to) Voter 2 C > A > B Voter 3 B > C > A Rather than a transitive order, we get a cycle: A is socially preferred to B (A defeats B), B to C, and C to A) => The social preference order under simple majority rule can be intransitive. (Arrow’s Impossibility Theorem: it is possible to observe “irrational” social preferences 26 under almost any social process.) Cycling is the major defect of majority voting as a choice mechanism (indeterminate outcome). Possible solutions 1. Stronger voting rules: such as 64% majority rule. 2. Representative democracy= voters choose representatives who choose policies where the representatives do not have exactly the same preferences over policies as the voters they represent=“delegation”= a principal-agent problem. 3. Restrict preferences such that simple majority rule give determinate outcome. 27 Median Voter Theorem (Black 1948): under certain conditions, majority voting leads to a stable equilibrium with the chosen policy being that favored by the median voter. Assumptions: 1. voters preferences are defined along a single dimension, 2. each voter’s preferences are single-peaked in that one dimension. Drawbacks: a) voting preferences cannot be represented as one-dimensional (= a single issue) b) preferences might no be defined in spatial terms (distance from the ideal 28 point = spatial voting) Public Goods Governments should provide public goods because 1. It is difficult to exclude free riders. 2. Provision of some public goods has strong distributional consequences. Recall: Characteristics of public goods: 1. Nonexcludable: cannot prevent individuals from consuming the good. 2. Nonrival: consumption by one individual does not preclude consumption by another Characteristics of common pool resources (Tragedy of the commons): 1. Nonexcludable: cannot prevent individuals from consuming the good. 2. Rival: consumption by one individual preclude consumption by another 29 Question : how much of a public good should be provided and how the burden of financing should be allocated? A social planner equates the sum of the marginal rates of substitution between the public good and a private good to the marginal rates of transformation between the two goods sum the benefits across all individuals and allocate taxes taking into account the individual budget constraints. Samuelson condition states: that is, the public good should be provided as long as the overall benefits to consumers (MBi: marginal benefit to each person of consuming one more unit of the public good) from that good are at least as great as the cost of providing it (MC). 30 Voluntary provision of public goods Group size is crucial in determining the likelihood of successful collective action. Prisoner’s Dilemma: an individual is always better off if he defects (free-rides)=> good will not be provided Coordination game: an individual benefits if everyone else acts the same way= defection is not the dominant strategy=> self-interested behavior supports a good equilibrium (requires good communication) The public goods game: defect if others provide the good and contribute if the good would not otherwise be 31 provided (noncooperation is not the dominant strategy) Interest Groups In a representative democracy interest groups influence political outcomes: either electoral outcomes through contributions or endorsements, or legislative decisions through lobbying. Traditional political science view: individuals with common goals form organizations to further their common interests or values not necessarily coincident with self-interest. Olson’s collective action problem Olson posed the necessary and sufficient conditions for the formation of interest groups: 1. Small size (free-riding can be detected and counted) 2. Their Public activities are by-products of their private efforts 3. Coercion is generally required for their organization and 32 maintenance. Consequences: interest groups retard economic growth and stifle the political and economic system in which they operate =>unless organized “distributional coalitions” are extraordinarily large and embracing their self-interests will surely be inimical to the public. Proposal: Restore free markets = informed citizens will demand that all special interests or rents be repealed. Critique: Olson ignores the role of the government. 33 The Chicago Model: Stigler, Posner, Barro, Peltzman Chicagoans  a) reject the notion that regulation grows out of public interest concerns b) identify the regulated industry as the source of demand for regulation and the government as the recipient of campaign contributions. Chicagoans include government in their analysis = regulators must respond to the demands of both consumers and regulated => efficient regulation requires that prices be raised only to the point where votes gained per dollar of price increase exactly offset votes lost among consumers. Critique: cannot predict which industries will be regulated, does not explain deregulation, does not incorporate the behavior of regulatory agencies to do better. 34 The Virginians: interest groups and rent seeking (Buchanan, Tullock, Tollison) The “interest group theory of government”: the government is not an institution that generates social welfare but rather provides a quasi-market setting for brokering wealth transfers and extorting rents. Rent-seeking: the political activity of individuals and groups who devote scarce resources to the pursuit of monopoly rights granted by governments 1. The expenditure of resources to gain a transfer is itself a social cost. 2. Rents represent a welfare loss on consumers and taxpayers. Types of rents: bribery, subsidies, tariffs farm or import quotas, etc Proposal: deny government actors the capacity to create rents through constitutional prescriptions 35 Chicago (reprise): Becker Pareto-optimal resolutions of externality situations can be and often are worked out between the affected parties without the help of the government. Side payments can internalize externalities in situations with sufficiently low transaction costs Coase theorem: in the absence of transaction and bargaining costs affected parties to an externality will agree on an allocation of resources that is both Pareto optimal and independent of any prior assignment of property rights Critique: the analysis does not explicitly incorporate a government. Proposal: The greater the number of interest groups, and the more balanced the competition among them, the more efficient are political outcomes. 36 Appendix II: How to measure democracy? Gastil (Freedom House) has created two measures of liberty: 1. Political rights 2. Civil liberties Political rights and civil liberties are ranked from 1 (the highest degree of liberty) to 7 (the lowest) The political rights ranking are based on the degree to which individuals in a state have control over those who govern. The civil liberties rankings purport to measure the rights of the individual (e.g. independence of the judiciary, freedom of the press, freedom of assembly and demonstration, freedom of political organization, free trade unions, free religious institutions). POLITY IV data set: a composite index that includes 1. presence of competitive political participation 2. guarantee of openness and competitiveness of executive recruitment 3. existence of institutionalized constraints on the exercise of executive power. Polity ranges from –10 (mostly autocratic) to 10 (mostly democratic).37 Winning coalition over the selectorate, W/S, measures the strength of the loyalty norm. As the size of the winning coalition increases relative to the selectorate, the loyalty of coalition members to the incumbent decreases and leader(s) must opt for policies that aim at providing more public goods in order to survive politically. “W”, the size of the winning coalition, is a composite index based on: (a) the variable REGTYPE (1=civilian; 2=military-civilian; 3=military; 4=other) taken from Banks’ data set; and (b) the variables XRCOMP (competitiveness of executive recruitment), XROPEN (openness of executive recruitment), and PARCOMP (competitiveness of participation) from the POLITY IV data set. “S”, the size of the selectorate (measures "the breadth of the selectiveness of the members of each country’s legislature" ), is the legislative selection (LEGSELEC) variable from the POLITY IV data set. LEGSELEC is a trichotomous variable that takes the value of 0 when there is no legislature; 1 when the legislature is chosen by either heredity, ascription or the executive; and 2 when members of the legislature are directly or indirectly selected by popular election. “W” and “S” are normalized to fall between 0 and 1. WoverS is, thus, W divided by (log(S+1)*10)/3 to avoid division by zero. 38 National Institutions and Global Public Goods Are democracies more cooperative in climate change policy? Forthcoming in: Michèle B. Bättig* and Thomas Bernauer**, ETH Zurich International Organization 63/2, 2009; available at http://www. ib.ethz.ch/docs until publication Abstract This paper examines whether democracies contribute more to the provision of global public goods. It thus contributes to the debate on the effects of domestic institutions on international cooperation. The focus is on human-induced climate change, in Stern’s (2007) words "the biggest market failure the world has ever seen". Using new data on climate change cooperation we study a cross-section of 185 countries in 1990-2004. The results show that the effect of democracy on levels of political commitment to climate change mitigation (policy output) is positive. In contrast, the effect on policy outcomes, measured in terms of emission levels and trends, is ambiguous. These results demonstrate that up until now the democracy effect has not been able to override countervailing forces that emanate from the free-rider problem, discounting of future benefits of climate change mitigation, and other factors that cut against efforts to reduce emissions. Even though democracies have had a slow start in moving from paper (policy output) to practice (policy outcomes), particularly in the transportation sector, we observe some encouraging signs. The main implication of our findings for research on international politics is that greater efforts should be made to study policy output and outcome side-by-side. This will help in identifying whether more democratic countries experience larger ‘words – deeds’ gaps also in other policy areas, and whether there are systematic differences of this kind between domestic and international commitments and across different policy areas. 1 Word count: 12’173 Keywords: global public goods, international cooperation, democracy, climate change, environment * Michèle B. Bättig holds a Ph.D. in environmental sciences from ETH Zurich. She is a project director at Econcept AG in Zurich, Switzerland, Lavaterstrasse 66, 8002 Zürich, Ph +41-44- 2867580, [email protected]. Corresponding author: **Thomas Bernauer is a professor of political science at ETH Zurich, Center for Comparative and International Studies (CIS) and Institute for Environmental Decisions (IED), Seilergraben 49, 8092 Zurich, Switzerland, Ph +41-44-6326466, F +41-44- 6321289, [email protected]. The authors are grateful to Michael Bechtel, Gary Goertz, Dieter Imboden, Detlef Jahn, Anna Kalbhenn, Vally Koubi, Mira Marcus-Kalish, Christian Martin, Katja Michaelowa, Ken Oye, Matthew Paterson, Michael Ross, Gabi Ruoff, Lena Schaffer, Detlef Sprinz, Jana von Stein, and the reviewers and editors of IO for highly useful comments on earlier versions of this paper. This paper was written in the context of the Swiss National Research Program on democracy in the 21st century. 2 1. Introduction Political scientists have, for analytical and normative reasons, invested much time and effort in trying to understand the consequences of democracy. A large amount of research concentrates on whether democratic systems perform better in terms of poverty reduction1, economic development2, and environmental quality3. At the international level, a vast literature focuses on the democratic peace hypothesis.4 IPE scholars have examined how democracy affects conflict and dispute settlement in the global trading system5, and how it influences compliance behavior in trade, monetary relations, and other areas6. IR scholars have also been interested in how democracy influences the propensity of states to engage in international commitments, e.g., in the form of joining international organizations and treaties.7 The existing literature shows that the implications of democracy for solving important policy problems, both domestically and internationally, vary considerably across levels of analysis, policy problems, and empirical definitions of policy-performance. For example, most studies on the democratic peace find positive effects for democratic dyads8, while the monadic effects remain disputed. The democracy effects on socio-economic development appear ambiguous.9 In the trade area, democracies tend to escalate disputes more often.10 Several studies on environmental performance have shown that democracies perform better in terms of domestic environmental quality11 and international commitment to environmental protection12, but the effects on transboundary environmental problem solving are less clear13. Our contribution fills an important gap in this literature by focusing on the implications of democracy for the provision of global public goods. Most of the existing literature concentrates on the provision of domestic public goods or the international behavior of countries vis-à-vis specific other countries. The empirical focus in this paper is on climate change. Within the past 25 years, the problem of human-induced climate change has evolved from a rather speculative scientific topic into one of the key issues on the global policy agenda. Nicholas Stern, former World Bank chief economist and author of an influential study on the economic effects of climate change, has called the latter "the biggest market failure the world has ever seen."14 The global scientific community, as organized through the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), is largely in agreement that anthropogenic causes, and emissions from the combustion of fossil fuels in particular, are to blame in large part for increasing temperatures in many areas of the world and on global average. It also agrees that the economic and social effects of human- induced climate change are grave and potentially disastrous, notably for societies with 1 See, for example, Ross 2006. 2 See, for example, Przeworski 2004. 3 See, for example, Ward 2008. 4 See, for example, Dorussen and Ward 2008. 5 See, for example, Busch 2000. 6 See, for example, Dai 2006; Simmons 2000. 7 See, for example, Hafner-Burton et al. 2008; Neumayer 2002. 8 See, for example, Dorussen and Ward 2008. 9 See Ross 2006; Bueno de Mesquita et al. 2001; Plümper and Martin 2003. 10 See, for example, Busch 2000. 11 See Ward 2008; Bernauer and Koubi 2008; Li and Reuveny 2006. 12 See Roberts et al. 2004; Neumayer 2002. 13 Bernauer and Kuhn 2008. 14 Presentation by N. Stern in the US Senate Energy and Natural Resources Committee, February 13, 2007. 3 insufficient means to adapt, and that reductions of greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions on a very large scale are required.15 The climate change issue also raises very interesting questions for scholars of comparative and international politics. It is one of the few policy-challenges in the international system that corresponds very closely to standard definitions of a global public good and the tragedy of the commons.16 Everyone producing GHG emissions, no matter where on Earth, contributes to increasing the risks of adverse climatic changes; everyone reducing GHG emissions contributes to the mitigation of such risks. The conventional logic of public goods theory holds that such problems are very difficult to solve17, particularly at the global level. There is no single country or agency that can act as an effective central enforcer; and the costs arising from aggregating national preferences, casting them into collectively binding global decisions, and implementing these policies are high. Moreover, the climate change problem is a long-term, inter-generational problem and involves big scientific challenges in trying to understand the benefits and costs of problem solving.18 The obvious difficulties in implementing the 1997 Kyoto Protocol and concluding a follow-up agreement for the post-2012 period demonstrate that the prediction of public goods theory is probably correct.19 Nonetheless, when we move from the global system perspective to cross-national comparisons we observe that national contributions to the global public good of climate change mitigation vary considerably, both with respect to political commitments and emission behavior. Table 1 illustrates this point. Table 1: Differences in climate change policy across countries country commitment GHG/cap change 1980-2004 (%) GHG/cap change 1990-2004 (%) Australia 0.65 0.7 0.9 Brasil 0.58 0.5 1.8 China 0.65 4 4.4 Germany 0.85 -1.3 -1.3 India 0.6 3.9 2.9 Indonesia 0.56 4.4 4.5 Iran 0.45 2.6 3.9 Japan 0.65 0.9 0.8 North Korea 0.52 -2.8 -4.6 Norway 0.83 1 1.8 UK 0.95 -0.5 -0.6 USA 0.63 -0.2 0.1 Note: The commitment variable ranges from 0 to 1, with 1 expressing the strongest political commitment to climate change mitigation. This variable is defined in the empirical design section below. GHG/cap is defined as the average annual change in per capita GHG emissions, excluding land use change, in CO2 equivalents. The source is CAIT 2008. 15 Stern 2007; and IPCC 2007. 16 Hardin 1968. 17 See, for example, Barrett 2005; Sandler 2004. 18 IPCC 2007. 19 See, for example, Cass 2006; Victor 2001. 4 For example, Germany scores high on political commitment and on reducing per capita greenhouse gas (GHG) emissions, and so does the UK. China, India, and Iran appear as laggard countries on both accounts. Australia, Brasil, Japan, and the USA occupy the middle ground. North Korea exhibits relatively low political commitment, but its emissions have declined. Conversely, Norway performs better with respect to political commitment than GHG reductions. Even more surprising from the viewpoint of public goods theory, several small countries and even some subnational political units (e.g., US cities and states) have adopted ambitious mitigation targets. Small actors can, individually, make only a small contribution to solving the overall problem and should thus have an especially strong incentive to free-ride on the efforts of bigger actors. Why, apparently, do some countries contribute more to the global public good of climate change mitigation than others? Can we say anything generic about the factors that motivate countries to behave more (or less) cooperatively? The economics literature views environmental outcomes (such as GHG emissions) as determined largely by economic factors, such as economic output, income, industrial structure, trade, etc.20 On occasion, economic models include some political control variables, but without much theoretical discussion. Moreover, economic models pay very little attention to policy output (political commitments), whereas the political science literature on environmental policy concentrates quite heavily on explaining policy output, rather than policy outcomes. We address both gaps in this paper. First, we concentrate on examining the effects of political institutions on climate change mitigation efforts. It is almost a truism among political scientists that domestic institutions affect international politics. But there is much less agreement, theoretically and empirically, on which particular institutional properties shape policy outputs and outcomes.21 We contribute to this research by studying whether and how democracy affects national behavior with respect to the provision of global public goods in the case of climate change mitigation. We focus on the effects of democracy because democracy is arguably the most fundamental feature that distinguishes national political systems in global comparison. Some of the theoretical arguments and empirical findings reported in the existing literature support the claim that democracy is conducive to international public goods provision in the environmental realm.22 But others are ambiguous or even negative.23 We will develop and test the hypothesis that, ceteris paribus, democracies are more cooperative with respect to climate change mitigation efforts. We theorize that the democracy effect hinges on whether the median voter and/or influential interest groups prefer more public goods provision and conclude that both the demand for and supply of climate mitigation measures are likely to be stronger in democracies. Furthermore, we argue that the democracy effect on environmental policy outcome is likely to be weaker than on policy output. The empirical testing is done on a cross-section of 185 countries in 1990-2004. We use new data on climate change cooperation that allows us to study the effects of democracy on policy output and policy outcomes side-by-side. The existing literature has focused either on one or the other dependent variable. The results confirm that distinguishing between policy output and policy 20 See, for example, Cole and Neumayer 2005; Antweiler et al. 2001. 21 See, for example, Przeworski 2004. 22 See, for example, Ward 2008; Neumayer 2002; Li and Reuveny 2006. 23 See, for example, Congleton 1992; Midlarsky 1998. 5 outcome is important. Democracies contribute more to the global public good in terms of policy output. In contrast, the democracy effect on policy outcomes is ambiguous. Our interpretation of these results is that in moving from political commitments to reductions of GHG emissions, the democracy effect has up to this point in time not been able to override countervailing forces that emanate from the free-rider problem, discounting of future benefits of climate change mitigation, and other factors that cut against efforts to reduce emissions. We also observe that democratic countries are experiencing greater difficulties in coping with emissions from transportation, where emission cuts are most likely to require restrictions on personal freedom (mobility). The main implication of our findings for research on international politics more broadly is that greater efforts should be undertaken to study policy output and outcome side-by-side. This will help in identifying whether more democratic countries experience larger ‘words – deeds’ gaps also in other policy areas, and whether there are systematic differences of this kind between domestic and international commitments and across different policy areas. 2. Theory If each country were equally affected by the free-rider problem associated with the production of global public goods, countries around the globe would, in the absence of other influences, be equally reluctant to contribute to the provision of such goods. Table 1 above suggests that this is not the case. Moreover, in climate change policy smaller countries whose emission reductions can contribute only minimally to solving the overall problem should have a strong motivation to wait and let the big countries move ahead first. A simple test questions this assumption. In the dataset we use for this paper (see section 3), the correlation between country size (in terms of population or GDP) and GHG emission growth rates as well as other indicators for countries’ performance in climate change mitigation efforts is close to zero. That is, on average, bigger countries are neither more nor less cooperative. A likely explanation for the cross-country variance we can observe is that institutions matter. Political institutions differ along many dimensions. We are interested in the effects of democracy. Democracy is arguably the most fundamental characteristic when comparing national political institutions globally.24 Our basic argument is that democracy has a positive effect on the demand for and supply of public goods, including global public goods such as climate change mitigation, and that this effect is likely to be stronger with respect to policy output than policy outcome. We arrive at this argument by first outlining the fundamental reasons for the expected positive democracy effect and then addressing two caveats. Olson, McGuire and Olson, Deacon, and other authors have argued that non-democratic polities tend to under-provide public goods.25 They are usually governed by small elites who seek to increase their personal wealth at the expense of the population. Hence they have little interest in foregoing private benefits, such as spending tax income on personal consumption or to buy loyalty from cronies, in order to invest in greater amounts of public goods – such as higher levels of environmental quality – that would benefit large parts of the population. That is, public goods 24 Przeworski 2004; Munck and Verkuilen 2002. Obviously, climate change is a global problem which requires cooperation by all countries worldwide, at the very least in terms relative to their GHG emissions. This justifies a global perspective. 25 Olson 1993; McGuire and Olson 1996; Deacon 1999. 6 are under-provided if opportunity costs associated with public goods provision are concentrated on a small elite, whereas the benefits are widely dispersed. In democracies, provision levels of public goods are influenced much more strongly by the preferences of the median voter or, in a more open formulation, prevailing interests among the electorate. The median voter (or the individual member of the electorate) in democracies incurs smaller opportunity costs from more environmental protection, relative to the median member of the ruling elite in a non-democracy. Collective action theory tells us that the former cost-benefit distribution is more conducive to public goods provision than the latter.26 An extension by Bueno de Mesquita et al. of the aforementioned argument focuses on how institutions influence the selection of political leaders and their incentives to provide public goods. 27 They claim that the extent to which governments provide public goods relative to private ones is determined by the size of the selectorate (those who affect the selection of and receive benefits from the leaders) and the size of the winning coalition (the subset of the selectorate that is needed to bring or keep leaders in office). In non-democracies, the winning coalition is usually small relative to the selectorate. In such systems, leaders thus need to deliver a relatively large amount of private goods to a small number of essential supporters to be able to remain in power. In contrast, in democracies the winning coalition is large relative to the selectorate. Political leaders in democratic systems do not have sufficient resources to reward their supporters with large amounts of private goods. Moreover, loyalty to the incumbent tends to be weaker in democracies than in autocracies (i.e., the probability of defection from winning coalitions is higher in democracies). Weaker loyalty of supporters forces democratic political leaders to deliver policies that provide relatively large amounts of public goods if they wish to survive politically. In autocracies, loyalty of elite members to incumbents is usually higher, and this motivates autocratic leaders to deliver more private goods to the small elite that keeps them in power. This optimism (at the theoretical level) about superior performance of democracies in terms of public goods provision has encountered criticism of various sorts. We address what we regard as the two most important caveats and conclude that only the second of these caveats requires a modification of the basic hypothesis. This caveat leads us to distinguish democracy effects on policy outputs from effects on policy outcomes. Caveat 1: the demand side The democracy effect argument presented above has a demand and supply side component. As to the supply side, it seems reasonable to assume that, at any given level of public demand, democratic leaders are likely to experience greater incentives than autocratic leaders to satisfy this demand. The demand side is more problematic. Extant research has not systematically dealt with the possibility that the median voter does not prefer more environmental quality, or that parochial interest groups dominate the political process. It is quite intuitive to assume that the median voter in a democracy will usually be more enthusiastic about public good provision than the median elite member in a non-democracy. Examples are public schools, public infrastructure (e.g. water supply and sanitation, hospitals, electricity, telecom), or clean air. We cannot assume automatically, however, that demand for any type of public good is greater in democracies than in autocracies. The existing literature does not 26 Stigler 1971; Olson 1968. 27 Bueno de Mesquita et al. 2003; see also Bernauer and Koubi 2008. 7 offer systematic empirical evidence on this issue.28 But we argue that there are several reasons for why the median voter in democracies will, on average, be ‘greener’ than the median elite member in non-democracies. Critics may object that the median elite member in a non-democracy tends to be wealthier and better educated than the median voter in a democracy and, assuming that environmental quality is a ‘normal’ good29, thus demands more environmental quality.30 At least four arguments cut against this idea. First, democracies are on average richer than autocracies.31 It is also well established in the literature that political participation of richer voters in democracies is higher. Consequently, the de facto median voter in democracies may not be poorer than the median elite member in non-democracies. Second, the median elite member in an autocracy will usually have more opportunities than the average member of the country’s population to shield herself from negative consequences that may arise from the under-provision of public goods. For example, she can move to a less polluted place within the country (or abroad). Wealthy persons in democracies can, of course, do the same. But this does not undermine demand for public goods provision to the same extent it does in non-democracies, where the median elite member has more political influence. Third, as noted above, opportunity costs of environmental policies are likely to be higher for the median elite member in a non-democracy than the median voter in a democracy. The anticipated net benefits of environmental policy will thus be smaller for the median elite member in a non-democracy. That is, even if the median elite member in an autocracy were greener than the democratic median voter, higher opportunity costs are more likely to lead her to negative expected net benefits of more environmental protection. Fourth, greater freedom to engage in research, communicate, exchange new evidence on environmental risks and travel to and obtain information from other countries is likely to make the public in democratic countries more aware of environmental problems and possibilities for their mitigation.32 This applies particularly to more complex, less visible, and less local risks (e.g., climate change). Criticism of the democracy-environment hypothesis has also focused on the role of interest groups, arguing that the preferences of the median voter may matter less in the policy-making process than the preferences of influential interest groups. Some critics have claimed that in advanced democracies ever greater interest group pluralism may reduce the provision of public goods.33 Politicians are forced to adopt more and more policies that cater to narrowly defined short-term interests of particular groups instead of longer-term interests of the public as a whole. Increasingly strong competition among interest groups may also make it harder to adopt policies that depart substantively from the status quo (gridlock problem). While it is possible that more mature democracies are characterized by more interest group activity, and increasing activity of this nature increases the likelihood of gridlock, we are not aware of any systematic studies that demonstrate such effects for a large sample of countries in environmental policy. 28 See Diekmann and Franzen 1999; Franzen and Meyer 2004. All large-scale surveys, such as the International Social Survey Program, focus primarily on democratic countries and do not allow us to determine whether, ceteris paribus, individual environmental preferences are also shaped by the political system. 29 See, for example, Cole and Neumayer 2005. 30 At least some forms of environmental degradation are characterized by an environmental Kuznets curve (EKC) (e.g., Grossman and Krueger 1995). Pollution first increases with income as people favor increased economic output over improvement of environmental quality. Once income has reached a higher level and basic material needs have been met, the willingness to invest more in “post-material” goods, such as environmental quality, increases. 31 Correlations between various measures of income and democracy are usually in the order of 0.4 to 0.6. 32 See also Payne 1995; Chadwick 1995. 33 See, for example, Olson 1982; Midlarsky 1998. 8 Critics of the democracy-environment hypothesis have also referred to the Olsonian notion that concentrated interests are easier to organize than diffuse interests. To the extent that the costs of slowing down or halting environmental degradation fall primarily on business, whereas the population as a whole benefits, we should expect that business holds less green preferences than the median voter, and that business is able to organize more effectively. Since virtually all highly democratic countries are advanced market economies, where the private sector plays the key role in innovation and economic growth, the combination of economic and political freedom may favor business interests over the interests of the median voter and may hence slow down progress in environmental policy. While the literature on interest group activity in economic policy- making offers some evidence for greater influence of business relative to other interests34, the environmental policy literature provides many examples where business interests have been overwhelmed by environmental interests35. In some cases, international cooperation – for example, the agreements to protect the stratospheric ozone layer – was even facilitated by “green and greedy” coalitions among business stakeholders and environmental interests.36 Rather than creating gridlock, increasing interest group pluralism may thus weaken the pro- business bias of interest group politics and hence promote green interests. If, for instance, greater pluralism in advanced democracies decreased the effectiveness of behind-the-doors lobbying by industry (whose preferences are presumably less green), environmental interest groups may in fact gain greater influence because industry has traditionally been more influential in behind-the- doors lobbying. Beck, Aerni and other authors have argued that in mature democracies, interest groups have in recent years been competing harder and harder for the attention of the public, and that public trust has become a key political resource in this process.37 Surveys have shown that in many countries the general public has more confidence in the information provided by NGOs than the information provided by business.38 In many cases, this loss of confidence in business as a stakeholder has put policy-makers under intense pressure to shield constituencies from an ever larger range of risks, including environmental risks, often at the expense of business interests. In addition, more pluralistic societies tend to exhibit lower levels of corruption. Corruption is one of the mechanisms through which business interests can obtain political influence, and it directs government resources to the production of private goods. In other words, if democracy promotes interest group pluralism, such pluralism may well lead to more rather than less provision of public goods. In summary, both demand and supply arguments point, on balance, towards a net democracy effect that is positive. Demand for environmental public goods provision is likely to be at least equally strong, and probably stronger in democracies than in non-democracies. And at any given level of public demand for public goods provision larger than the status quo (or greater than zero), democratic systems are more likely to supply the desired public goods. Caveat 2: national vs. global public goods, policy output vs. policy outcome A primary characteristic of climate change mitigation is that it is a global public good, i.e., the geographic scope of the problem is not congruent with national territories. Since democratic processes operate primarily within the domestic sphere, constituencies and politicians may be less 34 See, for example, Dryzek 1987. 35 See, for example, Vogel 2005; Bernauer and Caduff 2004; Bernauer 2003. 36 See, for example, Oye and Maxwell 1995. 37 Beck 1986; Aerni 2005. 38 Aerni 2005. 9 interested in resolving international or global relative to domestic problems.39 Consequently, we may find that democracy is helpful in dealing with local or national public goods problems, such as local air or water pollution, but not necessarily with complex global problems. However, this argument does not invalidate the democracy-environment hypothesis. Even if the global public goods nature of climate change mitigation weakens the democracy effect, this weakening should be viewed as relative to other public goods problems (notably local or national public goods). There is no reason to assume that any such weakening should be systematically stronger with respect to democracies than non-democracies. However, this caveat motivates us to pay more attention to the distinction between policy output and policy outcome. The problem of human-induced climate change has been on the global policy agenda only for around 15 years. And designing and implementing mitigation policies is complex, costly, and time-consuming. We should thus expect that democracy effects vary across policy output and policy outcome, with democracy having a weaker effect on policy outcomes. This possibility was noted by Neumayer several years ago with respect to other environmental degradation issues, but has been largely ignored in subsequent research. 40 The principal reason to study policy output and outcomes side-by-side and to expect a weaker democracy effect on outcomes is that the causal chain from environmental risks to public perceptions of such risks, to public demand for risk mitigation, and to policy output is shorter than the one leading from risk via policy output to policy outcome. Because of that, outcomes are, to the extent policies are effective, influenced by policy output, but also by a range of other factors, such as properties of the resource in question, mitigation costs, efficiency of implementing agencies, etc. Whereas policy outputs are largely under the control of policy- makers, policy outcomes may be affected also by factors that are outside their control. Under conditions of complete information policy makers will correctly determine the level of environmental protection that provides a net benefit (benefit from risk mitigation minus mitigation costs, including implementation costs) and meets median voter or prevailing interest group demands. They will also anticipate potential implementation problems and design effective monitoring and enforcement mechanisms to that end. But more often than not, such assumptions are more violated in the real world. In fact, a common observation in many studies on environmental policy is that policy-makers often respond quite well to public demands for more environmental protection, but tend to discount implementation problems, hoping that voters cannot identify these problems within a short-enough time-period to be able to punish policy- makers. In sum, the theoretical reasoning in this section produces two hypotheses that will be tested in the remainder of this paper. Hypothesis 1: More democratic countries exhibit stronger political commitment to climate change mitigation. Hypothesis 2: More democratic countries contribute more to climate change mitigation in terms of emission reduction. However, this positive democracy effect is weaker than the democracy effect on policy output. 39 See, for example, Paehlke 1996. 40 Neumayer 2002. 10 3. Empirical Design 3.1 Approach Focusing on climate change mitigation subjects the democracy-environment hypothesis to a particularly hard test. Because the focus is on national contributions to a global public good associated with substantial scientific uncertainty, a strong free-riding problem, and rather high mitigation costs, any significant, positive effect of democracy will be more convincing than in the case of more local, more visible, and scientifically less contested environmental degradation issues (e.g., local air or water pollution). The existing literature has produced contradictory results for the democracy effect in climate change mitigation policy. Congleton reports that democracies have higher levels of methane and CFC emissions per capita (his sample includes 118 countries in 1989).41 Midlarsky finds that more democratic countries have higher per capita CO2 emissions (his sample includes 98 countries in 1990).42 Gleditsch and Sverdrup find that democracy reduces CO2 emissions per capita (their sample includes 108 countries in 1990).43 Li and Reuveny obtain mixed results for CO2 emissions per capita (their sample includes 143 countries from 1961 to 1997): while the effect of a continuous indicator for democracy (Policy IV) is negative and significant, it is positive but not significant for a dichotomous indicator of democracy, and positive and significant for a dichotomous indicator of autocracy.44 As to policy output, a recent study by von Stein finds that democracy tends to have a positive effect on formal participation in global climate change policy (the sample includes 140 countries from 1992 to 2005).45 The empirical results for the democracy–climate policy hypothesis we just discussed are likely to differ due to differences in sampling (number of countries, cross-sectional analysis for individual years or time-periods vs. panel data analysis) and different definitions of the dependent variable (emission levels vs. trends, policy outcomes vs. policy output). We opt for a more comprehensive approach, focusing on 185 countries since 1990, when the climate change issue moved onto the global policy agenda, and examining policy output and outcome side-by-side. The analysis is cross-sectional because year-to-year changes on our dependent variables and the main dependent variable (democracy) are much smaller than cross-sectional variation. The data analysis relies on OLS with robust standard errors (Huber-White estimator). The dependent variable measures levels of public goods provision in climate change mitigation across countries. It is defined in four forms: in terms of indices for policy output and policy outcome, as well as indicators for emission levels and emission trends. The first index captures policy output, the second index and the two emissions indicators measure policy outcomes. We use three measures for policy outcomes to distinguish emission levels and emission trends because there is disagreement in the literature over which concept is more appropriate. Murdoch and Sandler and some other authors argue that pollution levels may not be appropriate when examining the effect of democracy on policy outcomes, and that one should study trends (or 41 Congleton 1992. 42 Midlarsky 1998. 43 Gleditsch and Sverdrup 2003. 44 Li and Reuveny 2006. 45 Stein 2008. 11 changes); that is, whether democracy contributes to emission reductions.46 We agree that the latter approach is better connected to the basic proposition: we do not argue that democracies are ‘cleaner’ at any given point in time; rather, we claim that democracies make a bigger effort to improve their environmental behavior. Our principal empirical models explain public goods provision as a function of democracy, controlling for climate change risk exposure, income, mitigation costs, trade, and other factors. The robustness of findings is assessed in a variety of ways. We start by excluding the richest countries from the sample. The reason is that virtually all of the richest countries are highly democratic. This may bias the results, even though we include income as a control variable. We also examine the robustness of findings by using alternative indicators for democracy, climate change risk exposure, income, mitigation costs, and trade, and by running the models for the four component indicators of the policy output index separately. In addition, we add a wide range of other control variables. We then re-assess the basic results by implementing the models for a climate change cooperation index from another source – that index includes emission levels, emission trends, and a policy component. The final part examines the effect of democracy on GHG emissions by particular economic sectors, notably electricity and heat production, and transportation. 3.2 Variables Table 2 offers on overview of variables and data sources. Table 2: Variables in the principal models Variable Definition Source output Index of cooperative behavior in Based on Bättig et al. 2008 climate change policy, defined in policy output terms; scale: 0…1, higher values indicate more cooperative behavior; 1990-2005 outcome Index of cooperative behavior in Based on Bättig et al. 2008 climate change policy, defined in emissions related terms; scale: 0…1, higher values indicate more cooperative behavior; 1990-2003 emisslevel Natural log of CO2 emissions per Based on CAIT, http://cait.wri.org/ capita; 1990-2004 averages; transformed to 0…1 scale and inverted; higher values indicate more cooperative behavior 46 Murdoch and Sandler 1997. Neumayer (2002:144) points to this problem in studies by Midlarsky (1998), Torras and Boyce (1998), and Barrett and Graddy (2000). 12 emisstrend Average annual growth rate of CO2 Based on CAIT, http://cait.wri.org/ emissions p.c.; 1990-2004 averages; transformed to 0…1 scale and inverted; higher values indicate more cooperative behavior democracy Political rights index by Freedom Freedom House 2006, House; 1990-2005 averages; scale of http://www.freedomhouse.org original data inverted, 1…7, higher values indicate more democracy cci Climate Change Index; index of Bättig et al. 2007 climate change risk exposure; scale: 0…1, higher values indicate greater risk for the respective country income, GDP per capita in PPP (1990 intl. Maddison 2007, incomesquare Geary-Khamis dollars); log of http://www.ggdc.net/maddison/ averages for 1990-2003 or most recent year for which data was available income=ln(gdpcapppp1990) incomesquare=(ln(gdpcapppp1990))^2 GDPgrowth Average annual growth of GDP per World Development Indicators, capita http://www.worldbank.org/data; Maddison 2007, http://www.ggdc.net/maddison/ CO2cap1990 CO2 emissions per capita in 1990 CAIT, http://cait.wri.org/ oilgascoal Sum of oil, gas and coal production Based on data from BP Statistical per capita (all in mio. tons of oil Review of World Energy, June 2007; equivalents); 1990-2005 (or most http://www.bp.com/statisticalreview recent year) averages tradeopen Trade openness (imports plus exports Gleditsch, divided by GDP), 1990-2000 http://privatewww.essex.ac.uk/ ~ksg/exptradegdp.html Policy output measures the extent of political, legal, and administrative commitments to the UN- based climate change mitigation process. This index is based on Bättig et al. (2008) and includes the following indicators: (1) UNFCCC: this indicator is composed of two equally weighted indicators measuring whether the country has ratified the UN Framework Convention on Climate Change, UNFCCC (yes=1/no=0) and how fast it has done so (declining scale from 1992 through 1997); (2) Kyoto: this indicator is composed of two equally weighted indicators measuring whether the country has ratified the Kyoto Protocol (yes=1/no=0) and how fast it has done so (declining scale from 1998 through 2005); (3) Reporting: this indicator is composed of two equally weighted indicators measuring whether the country has submitted the latest national climate report (yes=1/no=0) and whether it has done so in time; (4) Funding: this indicator 13 measures how often a country has made its financial contributions to the UNFCCC secretariat in time between 1996 and 2005 (linear scale according to the number of contributions in time). The values of the four components are added with equal weight since there is no compelling argument for why one or the other component should be more important. The values of the policy output index are standardized on a 0 to 1 scale. Higher values indicate more cooperative behavior. Policy outcomes are measured in three ways. The policy outcome index assesses primarily emission trends. It is composed of two elements: 1990 levels of CO2 emissions per capita in relation to GDP per capita; and the trend of CO2 emissions per capita in relation to GDP per capita between 1990 and 2002. The latter element of the index captures the trend of emissions compared to a quadratic function fitted into the emissions of 13 EU countries in the 1870 to 2002 period. That is, it uses a fitted environmental Kuznets curve as a benchmark and measures how well a country performs in relation to this benchmark. Relating emission trends and levels to income offers an indication of how well countries are coping with the challenge of growing economically without excessively damaging the natural environment. The values of the index, whose construction is described in greater detail in Bättig et al., are standardized on a 0 to 1 scale.47 Higher values indicate more cooperative behavior. In addition, we use two indicators whose definition is more simple and straightforward: CO2 emissions per capita (emisslevel), and growth of CO2 emissions per capita (emisstrend). For both indicators we use 1990-2004 averages. To facilitate comparison with the policy output and outcome indices, we invert the scale of emisslevel and emisstrend, so that higher values indicate lower emissions and thus greater contributions to the global public good. We standardize the values to a 0…1 scale. We would like to emphasize at this point that the three policy outcome variables measure emission behavior in the broadest possible manner; they do not measure compliance with Kyoto commitments or the effectiveness of such commitments. Democracy is measured with the Freedom House political rights index.48 We use this index primarily because it is available for a larger number of countries and more recent years than the Polity IV index and other indices for democracy. We invert the original scale, making 1 the least and 7 the most democratic score, and use 1990-2005 averages. All models include a set of control variables. The Climate Change Index (cci) is based on predictions of future annual and seasonal temperature and precipitation. It captures the degree of future climate change relative to today’s natural variability and is calculated on the basis of three GCM simulations of the 21st century under the IPCC emission scenarios A2 and B2. While this indicator does not measure climate impacts (e.g., in terms of how many percentages climate change could reduce GDP within particular time-frames) it provides a reasonably clear picture of how strong climatic change in individual countries is likely to be.49 Higher values on a 0 to 1 scale indicate higher risk exposure of a country. We include this control variable because most theories of international environmental cooperation argue that risk-exposure plays a central role in accounting for why countries respond differently to any given category of international problems.50 We expect the index to have a positive effect on cooperative behavior. Income is measured as the natural logarithm of GDP per capita (PPP, 1990 USD). We use averages for 1990-2002 (or the most recent year for which data is available). We also include the 47 Bättig et al. 2008. 48 Freedom House 2006. 49 For a more detailed description, see Bättig et al. 2007. 50 See, for example, Sprinz and Vaahtoranta 1994; Social Learning Group 2001. 14 squared value of this indicator to account for the possibility of an environmental Kuznets curve.51 We expect a positive, linear effect of income on policy output. Except for the models including outcome as the dependent variable, the models also include economic growth (gdpgrowth). For models including emission levels and trends as dependent variables we expect non-linear effects of GDP growth. At lower levels of income, growth is likely to increase emissions. At higher levels of income, it is likely to be associated with non-increasing or decreasing emissions. All models include a trade openness variable (exports plus imports divided by GDP, tradeopen). The existing literature52 is divided on whether trade effects are positive, negative, or insignificant. The main reason for uncertainty about the direction and size of trade effects is that trade may have effects on economic structure (composition), economic output (scale), and income53; it is empirically open which of the three effects dominates or whether they offset each other. We include a variable that proxies for mitigation costs. There is no agreement in the literature on how to estimate mitigation costs.54 We opt for a simple indicator – CO2 emissions per capita in 1990 (CO2cap1990) – but assess the impact of alternative measures in our robustness checks. We acknowledge that the effect of the chosen indicator may cut both ways. Countries with higher p.c. emissions may be less energy-efficient and may thus find it easier to reduce emissions, at least for some time. Conversely, to the extent international notions of fairness demand that in the long term such countries have to bring their emissions down to some uniform per capita level (many proposals refer to this as ‘carbon justice’ and often refer to 2-5 tons of CO2 p.c. and year), they may be less willing to cooperate. We use this indicator in all models except those for the policy outcome index – CO2 emissions p.c. are used in the construction of that index. Instead, we use fossil fuel production in those models, assuming that producers of fossil fuels (oil, gas, coal) will, for economic reasons, be less interested in contributing to climate change mitigation. This indicator is defined as total fossil fuel production (oil, coal, gas, all in oil equivalents) per capita (oilgascoal).55 The policy outcome index is included as a control variable in the models for emission levels and trends, assuming that politically more committed countries are performing better in political outcome terms as well. 4. Results We start by estimating the effect of democracy on four indicators for national contributions to global climate change mitigation: (1) policy output; (2) policy outcome; (3) emission levels (emisslevel); (4) changes in emission levels (emisstrend). All dependent variables are scaled 51 A common assumption in the environmental economics literature is that pollution first grows with income and, at some point that may vary across pollutants and countries, starts to decline. If this inverted U-shape (the so-called environmental Kuznets curve, EKC) effect exists, the income variable should have a negative and the squared income variable a positive coefficient. 52 See, for example, Cole and Neumayer 2005. 53 Antweiler et al. 2001. 54 See, for example, Stern 2007. 55 We do not use fossil fuel consumption because the available data is less reliable and rather incomplete, and because GHG emissions are directly related to fossil fuel consumption. 15 from 0 to 1, with higher values indicating larger contributions to the global public good.56 Table 3 shows the estimates. Democracy has a positive and significant effect on policy output and on the emission level variable. These effects are substantial: a one point increase in democracy (ca. 17% on the 1…7 scale) produces a 3.2% increase in policy output and a 1 % increase in policy outcome defined in terms of emission levels. If democracy levels change from those of China (minimum) to those of Canada (maximum), this increases policy output by 19% and improves emission levels by 6 %. These results support hypotheses 1 and 2. Hypothesis 1 (as tested in model 1, Table 3) claims that more democratic countries exhibit greater political commitment to climate change mitigation. Hypothesis 2 (as tested in model 3, Table 3) holds that more democratic countries perform better in reducing their emissions, though this effect is likely to be weaker. Indeed, the democracy coefficient in model 3 is significantly smaller than in model 1. Table 3: Effects of democracy (1) (2) (3) (4) output outcome emisslevel emisstrend democracy 0.0312*** -0.0227*** 0.0095** 0.0025 [0.0088] [0.0087] [0.0038] [0.0059] cci -0.1431 0.1192 -0.0063 -0.1774*** [0.0940] [0.1157] [0.0401] [0.0521] income 0.0599*** -0.7305*** -0.1189 [0.0191] [0.0848] [0.1260] income^2 0.0368*** 0.0053 [0.0053] [0.0075] GDPgrowth -0.0068 0.0040** -0.0144* [0.0053] [0.0018] [0.0074] CO2cap1990 -0.0050* -0.0142*** 0.0072*** [0.0027] [0.0021] [0.0016] oilgascoal -442.0084*** [111.0305] tradeopen -0.0436** -0.1115** 0.0121 0.0070 [0.0201] [0.0524] [0.0168] [0.0153] output 0.1378 0.0483 -0.0678 [0.0883] [0.0417] [0.0629] constant 0.1211 0.6017*** 3.8572*** 1.2871** [0.1337] [0.0888] [0.3437] [0.5322] observations 172 182 172 171 R-squared 0.325 0.207 0.881 0.288 Robust standard errors in brackets. * significant at 10%; ** significant at 5%; *** significant at 1%. 56 The dataset, Stata do-files and a paper presenting additional empirical results (e.g., robustness checks) are available from the authors. 16 The effects of democracy on the policy outcome index and emission trends (models 2 and 4, Table 3) cut against hypothesis 2.57 The effect of democracy on the former is negative and significant, the effect on the latter is positive but insignificant. That is, the results shown in Table 3 support hypothesis 1, but offer only very limited support for hypothesis 2. The coefficients for the climate change index show that risk exposure does not motivate countries to contribute to the global public good. In the model for emission trends, the effect is even negative and significant. We interpret this finding in the sense that available scientific information on climate change has not (yet?) spurred sufficient public demand for risk mitigation, that the free rider problem reduces demand for and supply of risk mitigation measures, or both. As expected, the income effect on policy output is positive and significant in the full sample and the reduced sample.58 We also implemented the model with income divided by the Gini index to approximate the income of the median voter. The results (not shown here) are very similar. The results are quite consistent across the full sample and the reduced sample. The environmental Kuznets curve effect is strong in the models for emission levels and follows the expected pattern: emissions increase with income, and at high levels of income start to decrease. This effect is similar for emission trends, but much weaker. Economic growth has a heterogeneous effect. It has no significant effect on policy output, a positive effect in terms of lower emission levels, but an adverse effect on emission trends. The expected Kuznets curve effect for GDP growth does not show up in our data: the coefficients for GDP growth have the same signs in the full sample and the lower income group (not shown here). We cross-checked this result using an interaction between income and growth. The results (not shown here) were very similar. Per capita CO2 emission levels in 1990 have a significant, negative effect on policy output and the emission level variable, but a significant, positive effect on the emission trend variable. Production of fossil fuels has the expected (negative effect) on public goods provision. The same effect shows up when we use this variable also in the other models in lieu of 1990 CO2 emissions per capita. The negative effect of trade openness on policy output supports the regulatory chill over the trading up hypothesis.59 Countries that are more open to international trade are more reluctant to commit to climate change mitigation. Our data can also be used to test whether democracies find it easier or harder to bring their self- selected political commitment levels in line with their environmental behavior. To start with, the effect of the policy output variable in the emission level and trend models is positive in most of our models, but statistically significant in only one of them. This suggest that, for all countries in our sample, ‘words and deeds’ are not strongly related. What role does democracy play in this context? To assess this effect we constructed a new dependent variable. This variable is defined as the policy outcome (defined as the sum of the emisslevel and emisstrend variable, standardized to a 0 to 1 scale) minus the policy output variable. -1 on this scale identifies countries that are investing far more in words than in deeds, +1 identifies countries at the opposite end. When we implement the exact same model as for emisslevel for this new dependent variable, we find that both democracy and income have a significant negative effect (results not shown here). That is, rich and democratic countries are particularly prone to perform better at the political commitment level than in terms of cutting their emissions. 57 The overall properties of model 2 are somewhat problematic because fossil fuel production (whose distribution is very skewed) is by far the strongest determinant. 58 Multicollinearity problems in the models reported in Table 3 are minor. The highest bivariate correlations among explanatory variables are those between income and democracy (0.59) and income and per capita CO2 levels in 1990 (0.62). 59 Vogel 1995. 17 Our results for the policy output index correspond to findings by von Stein (2008), which to our knowledge is the most sophisticated large-N study focusing on policy output in the climate change area.60 The results for emissions related behavior are helpful in addressing contradictory findings by Gleditsch and Sverdrup, Li and Reuveny, Congleton, and Midlarsky.61 As noted above, focusing on emission trends rather than levels may offer a more appropriate test of the democracy-environment hypothesis. We should expect that, ever since climate change policy emerged on the international agenda (the mid to late 1980s), democracies have been doing a better job in dealing with the problem, irrespective of whether their emission levels were higher or not at the outset of the process (we control for this possibility by including 1990 CO2 emissions per capita). The democracy coefficient in the model for the policy outcome index turns out to be negative and significant, in the model for emission trends it is positive but insignificant. The overall conclusion is that we should be very cautious and perhaps even skeptical in interpreting the positive democracy effect on emission levels as confirmation of the democracy- environment hypothesis. How robust are these results? For a start we examined whether excluding the richest 10% of the sample (most of these countries are highly democratic) changes the results. It does not. We then explored whether outliers and/or skewed distributions of variables have affected the results, but did not identify significant problems of this kind. For example, we examined the effects of dropping particular countries that appeared as outliers. The results are robust to excluding Iceland, Suriname, and Andorra. These three countries are outliers on the policy output, democracy, and climate risk variables. Iceland scores very high on democracy and policy output, but very low on climate risk; Suriname scores very high on climate risk and very low on policy output. Andorra scores very high on democracy, but very low on policy output. We then cross- examined the results in five more ways: by using six alternative indicators for democracy; by separately estimating the effects of democracy on the four component indicators of the policy output index; by using alternative indicators for climate risk, income, mitigation costs, and trade openness; by adding additional control variables; and by defining an overall climate policy performance index, implementing the explanatory model for this dependent variable and a climate policy performance measure provided by another source (Germanwatch), and comparing the results. None of these robustness checks changes the conclusions in important ways. We focus on the last robustness check in some more detail.62 We replace our indicators for the dependent variable with the hitherto most widely used alternative index for national performance in climate change policy, the Climate Change Performance Index (CCPI) by Germanwatch (2008). This index combines data for emission levels (30% weight), emission trends (50% weight), and climate policy (20% weight). Its 2008 version is available for 56 countries (compared to 180+ countries in our dataset). We standardize the CCPI to the same scale (0…1, 1 indicating strongest performance) used for all definitions of the dependent variable in this paper (GWscore). For purposes of comparison, we construct a similar index based on our own dataset, with the same weights of the three components (output=20%, emisstrend=50%, emisslevel=30%, CPperform). 60 The income indicators are not used in the models with outcome as the dependent variable because the latter’s construction includes income. The squared income indicator is not used in models with output as the dependent variable because there is no theoretical or empirical argument for assuming a non-linear effect. 61 Gleditsch and Sverdrup 2003; Li and Reuveny 2006; Congleton 1992; Midlarsky 1998. 62 The results of other robustness checks are available from the authors. 18 Table 4: Results for overall indices of climate policy performance. (1) (2) GWscore CPperform democracy 0.0520*** 0.0154*** [0.0171] [0.0055] cci -0.3445* -0.1883*** [0.1766] [0.0557] income -0.8427 -0.5024*** [0.6667] [0.1146] income^2 0.0421 0.0264*** [0.0373] [0.0069] GDPgrowth -0.0285** -0.0121** [0.0133] [0.0056] CO2cap1990 -0.0289*** -0.0028* [0.0064] [0.0017] tradeopen 0.1436** -0.0030 [0.0564] [0.0180] constant 4.8564 2.9467*** [2.9606] [0.4688] observations 55 171 R-squared 0.583 0.452 Robust standard errors in brackets. * significant at 10%; ** significant at 5%; *** significant at 1%. Table 4 shows that the results for the democracy effect are positive and significant for both overall indices of climate policy performance. The caveat is, however, that such overall measures obfuscate important differences between policy output and policy outcome, as shown in Table 3. We also replaced our policy output index with the policy component of the Germanwatch index. The results (not shown here) for the democracy effect are the same as for the models including our policy output index. As shown above, democracies find it particularly difficult to match ‘words and deeds’. The final step in our analysis offers at least a partial explanation for this. Some studies suggest that advanced industrialized countries experience particularly serious difficulties in cutting emissions in the transportation sector, whereas poorer countries are experiencing higher growth rates in GHG emissions from electricity and heat production. 63 Large point sources (such as thermal power plants) are, in technical and monitoring/enforcement terms, easier to control than transportation. Moreover, democratic governments may find it harder to restrict individual freedom by imposing constraints on personal mobility. To the extent these assumptions hold true, we should observe a negative effect of democracy on emissions from transportation. Table 5 offers support for this argument. 63 See, for example, Jahn 2008; IEA 2007. 19 Table 5: Democracy effects on CO2 emission trends in electricity&heat production and transport (1) (2) CO2electr&heat CO2transport democracy 0.0045 -0.0238* [0.0082] [0.0120] cci -0.1273 -0.0143 [0.1196] [0.0734] income -0.4769** -0.1192 [0.1849] [0.2140] income^2 0.0275** 0.0102 [0.0109] [0.0132] GDPgrowth -0.0034 -0.0122 [0.0067] [0.0117] CO2electr&heat1990 0.0122*** [0.0043] CO2transport1990 0.0015 [0.0168] tradeopen -0.0147 -0.0112 [0.0292] [0.0305] output -0.0214 -0.1552* [0.0570] [0.0813] constant 2.6192*** 1.0396 [0.7615] [0.8586] observations 103 107 R-squared 0.177 0.170 Robust standard errors in brackets. * significant at 10%; ** significant at 5%; *** significant at 1%. The dependent variable is defined as the average annual growth of CO2 emissions per capita in 1990-2004 from energy and heat production as well as transportation. Again, we invert the scale and standardize the dependent variables to a 0 to 1 range; higher values indicate smaller or negative emission growth rates. As to CO2 emissions from electricity and heat production, the biggest effects emanate from 1990 emission levels and the EKC. Countries that had higher emission levels per capita in this sector in 1990 experienced lower growth rates thereafter. And poorer countries have experienced higher emission growth rates than richer countries. Interestingly, democratic countries experience greater difficulties in cutting emissions in the transportation sector. The effect of democracy is negative and significant.64 Moreover, better performance in policy output terms has a significant, negative effect on performance in terms of emission trends in the transportation sector. This finding shows that the ambiguous democracy affect on policy outcomes shown in Table 3 may, at least to some extent, stem from the fact that democracies are finding it particularly difficult to restrict individual freedom and curb transport- related emissions. We return to this issue in the conclusion. 64 The 95% confidence interval for the democracy coefficient includes zero, but when we drop 1990 CO2 levels because of their high correlation with income, the coefficient becomes significantly different from zero. 20 5. Conclusion In focusing on the implications of democracy for the provision of global public goods this paper addresses an important gap in the IR and comparative politics literature. The latter deals primarily with the effects of democracy on domestic public goods provision and dyadic international behavior. We have concentrated on climate change, one of the most important and complex global public goods challenges facing mankind. The empirical testing was done on a cross- section of 185 countries in 1990-2004. The results show that the effect of democracy on political commitment to global public goods provision (policy output) is positive. In contrast, the democracy effects on policy outcomes, measured in terms of emission levels and trends, are ambiguous. The analysis of sectoral emissions suggests that the ambiguous democracy effect in the analysis of total emissions is at least in part due to the negative democracy effect on emissions from transportation. These results demonstrate that, in moving from political commitments to GHG reductions, the democracy effect has up to this point in time not been able to override countervailing forces that emanate from the free-rider problem, discounting of future benefits of climate change mitigation, and other factors that cut against efforts to reduce emissions. The research reported in this paper has interesting implications for IR theory as well as climate change policy. The implications for IR theory are that ambiguous findings in the existing literature with respect to the effects of democracy on domestic public goods provision and dyadic international behavior can be identified also in the area of global public goods provision, particularly for policy outcomes. Studying political commitment and environmental behavior side-by-side thus produces insights that are missing in studies that concentrate only on one or the other dependent variable. In climate change policy, democracies are clearly more responsive at the political commitment than at the problem solving level, not only in absolute terms, but also relative to non-democracies. It will be interesting to explore whether more democratic countries experience larger ‘words – deeds’ gaps also in other policy areas, and whether there are systematic differences of this kind between domestic and international commitments and across different policy areas. The comparative politics and political economy literature allows for two competing hypotheses.65 One assumes that in democracies with a well-informed electorate and high levels of competition for political offices, policy-makers who promise more than they can implement experience political costs, for example an increased risk of losing elections. The other assumes that growing mediatization of politics and other factors that have increased the extent of competition for electoral support motivate policy-makers to become more “adventurous” with respect to political commitments. And to the extent voters are myopic and “overdosed” by competing information and political claims, policy-makers in advanced democracies can get away lightly with increased ‘words-deeds’ gaps. The recent IR literature tends to side with the first assumption. Several authors have argued that democracies have stronger domestic enforcement mechanisms than non-democracies, and that their decisions to engage in international commitments will thus be more closely aligned with 65 See, for example, Persson and Tabellini 2000; Kriesi 2008. 21 policy outcomes.66 Von Stein hypothesizes that “democracies…are more likely to keep their international promises – in large part because they only make promises they know they can keep.”67 The approach taken in this paper, which uses a unified analytical framework to study policy output, outcome, and gaps between the two, helps in testing this claim without narrowing the focus to legally binding obligations and formal compliance. Hence it is more in line with the recent literature on the effectiveness of international regimes, which conceptualizes effectiveness primarily in terms of problem solving rather than legal compliance.68 In using self-selected political commitment levels rather than formal treaty obligations as the benchmark, it also avoids the “constrain or screen” problem inherent in studies focusing on formal treaty commitments and compliance.69 In contrast to empirical results on (positive) democracy effects on compliance in the human rights and monetary policy area70, our analysis shows that democracy is associated with a bigger implementation gap in climate change policy. This contrasting evidence appears quite worrying from a normative perspective. The remainder of this section thus concentrates on its policy implications. In climate change policy, democracies have obviously had a slow start in moving from paper (policy output) to practice (policy outcomes). This should not come as a great surprise. Climate change is a much more complex challenge than most local or regional environmental degradation issues, such as air and water pollution. It is also characterized by a global free-rider problem. However, there are signs that more democratic countries are likely to perform better over the long run in policy-outcome terms as well. As argued in the theory section, public and interest group demand for climate change mitigation is likely to be stronger in democracies than in non- democracies. The available empirical evidence in fact suggests that public concern over climate change risks tends to be higher in democracies, independently of income. And so is environmental NGO activity.71 Moreover, democracies tend to have higher income levels, and the available data shows that the environmental Kuznets curve for GHG emissions has already reached a turning point in most of the very rich and democratic countries. Democracies are, independently of income, also more active in environmental monitoring and research and development72 – this increases knowledge about risks and generates new technologies that are 66 See, for example, von Stein 2005a. 67 Von Stein 2005a. 68 See, for example, Helm and Sprinz 2000; Young 2007. 69 Von Stein 2005b; Simmons and Hopkins 2005. 70 See, for example, von Stein 2005a; Simmons 2000. 71 The lack of large-N data for public demand for climate change mitigation prevents us from systematically testing whether democracy has a positive effect on such demand. However, we can muster some, albeit sketchy support from surveys, e.g. the one carried out in ca. 40 countries by the Program on International Policy Attitudes (http://www.pipa.org/). The PIPA survey data covers the years 2003 and 2006. The respondents were asked whether “climate change or global warming, due to the greenhouse effect“ is a serious problem. This survey measures public concern over climate change risks. We regressed this data on income and democracy and found that democracy has a significant, positive effect on such concern. We also examined the determinants of Greenpeace membership per capita (von Stein 2008) and included this indicator in the models reported in Table 3. Greenpeace is well-known for its strong position in favor of large GHG emission cuts. Its membership may serve as a proxy for how strong interest group pressure for climate change mitigation is. We found that democracy is a significant, positive predictor of Greenpeace membership independently of other potential determinants (e.g., income). In adding this indicator to the models rep

Use Quizgecko on...
Browser
Browser