Philosophy of Knowledge Quiz
49 Questions
0 Views

Choose a study mode

Play Quiz
Study Flashcards
Spaced Repetition
Chat to Lesson

Podcast

Play an AI-generated podcast conversation about this lesson

Questions and Answers

What did Plato define knowledge as?

  • Justified true belief (correct)
  • Justified false belief
  • Belief without justification
  • Propositional true knowledge

Which philosophical challenge undermined the tripartite definition of knowledge?

  • Realism
  • Gettier cases (correct)
  • Epistemic relativism
  • Nominalism

Which of these is NOT one of the proposed alternative accounts of knowledge after Gettier's critique?

  • Infallibilism
  • Reliabilism
  • JTB + No false lemmas
  • Pragmatism (correct)

What type of knowledge does the tripartite definition specifically refer to?

<p>Propositional knowledge (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

According to the tripartite definition, which of the following is a necessary condition for knowledge?

<p>Belief (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is the key focus of the definitions of knowledge discussed?

<p>To rule out Gettier cases while capturing valid knowledge (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which definition adds the condition of 'no false lemmas' to the tripartite definition?

<p>JTB + No false lemmas (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What are the components of the tripartite definition of knowledge?

<p>Belief, truth, justification (A)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which condition is NOT considered necessary for knowledge according to some arguments?

<p>Justification (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Gettier cases illustrate the problem with which aspect of justified true belief?

<p>The occurrence of luck (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

In Smith's first Gettier case, why does his belief about Jones's coins fail to count as knowledge?

<p>Smith's conclusion was based on mere luck. (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What element of Gettier's second case involves disjunction introduction?

<p>Brown being in Barcelona (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

According to the tripartite definition, which of the following is required for a belief to qualify as knowledge?

<p>It must be justified. (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which philosopher argued that justification is not necessary for knowledge?

<p>Zagzebski (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which of the following statements exemplifies a justified true belief?

<p>I know it is raining because I see water droplets. (A)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is a common misconception students might have regarding Gettier cases?

<p>They show that luck can invalidate a belief's status as knowledge. (A)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What does Gettier's work challenge regarding the conventional understanding of knowledge?

<p>The sufficiency of justified true belief (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What would be an example of a belief that could potentially be known without belief?

<p>Knowing the capital of France but forgetting it. (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which statement best summarizes a key implication of Gettier's cases?

<p>Knowledge requires more than justified true belief. (A)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What logical principle is used in Gettier's second case to form a new belief?

<p>Disjunction introduction (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

In the context of knowledge debates, what does 'truth' imply according to Zagzebski?

<p>It is not explicitly required. (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

How can we characterize Smith's belief about whether Jones owns a Ford in the second Gettier case?

<p>It is justified and true due to luck. (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What does Zagzebski argue about the relationship between truth and the third condition in defining knowledge?

<p>They are simply added together but not connected. (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

According to Zagzebski, what constitutes James's knowledge of P?

<p>James believes that P, and his belief arises from an act of intellectual virtue. (A)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is the meaning of 'aptness' in Sosa's virtue epistemology?

<p>The belief must be true as a result of the believer's intellectual virtues. (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What problem does virtue epistemology face regarding young children or animals?

<p>It seems to rule out the possibility that they possess knowledge. (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Infallibilism asserts that for a belief to count as knowledge, it must be:

<p>True and justified to the point of certainty. (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is a potential criticism of infallibilism?

<p>It sets the bar for knowledge certainty too high. (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which of the following scenarios exemplifies a failure of Sosa's definition of knowledge?

<p>An expert fails to recognize a false statement. (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What does the analogy of moral virtue illustrate in the context of Zagzebski's analysis?

<p>Only successful actions can count as virtuous. (A)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What distinguishes Sosa's definition of knowledge from traditional definitions criticized by Zagzebski?

<p>Sosa connects truth directly to the exercise of intellectual virtues. (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

How does the 'fake barn county' example challenge traditional concepts of knowledge?

<p>It emphasizes that true beliefs can arise from luck. (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

In Gettier cases, what is the primary issue with the definition of knowledge?

<p>Beliefs can be justified without being true. (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is the concern with the certainty requirement in infallibilism?

<p>It is difficult to achieve and leaves little that can be known. (A)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What role do virtues play in Zagzebski's analysis of knowledge?

<p>They motivate the pursuit of truth and enable success in forming beliefs. (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What additional condition does the no false lemmas definition of knowledge include?

<p>The belief must not be inferred from anything false (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which scenario illustrates a problem for the no false lemmas definition of knowledge?

<p>Henry believes there is a barn based on seeing a fake barn. (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

According to reliabilism, how is knowledge defined?

<p>A belief caused by a reliable method (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is one of the significant advantages of reliabilism over other definitions of knowledge?

<p>It accounts for knowledge in children and animals. (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is a problem that arises for reliabilism using the fake barn county example?

<p>It suggests that a false belief can be knowledge. (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is virtue epistemology primarily concerned with?

<p>Intellectual virtues related to knowledge (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Who argues that 'true belief + some third condition' will always fall victim to Gettier-style cases?

<p>Linda Zagzebski (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What does Zagzebski's formula for Gettier cases require to construct a challenge to knowledge?

<p>Bad luck leading to false belief (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What does a reliable method produce according to reliabilism?

<p>A high percentage of true beliefs (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which of the following does NOT count towards knowledge in the context of the content provided?

<p>A belief inferred from a false lemma (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Based on the JTB+N definition, which condition might still lead to a misconception of knowledge?

<p>Belief must avoid bad luck (C)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Which definition would classify Henry’s belief about the barn incorrectly as knowledge?

<p>Reliabilism (D)</p> Signup and view all the answers

An intellectual virtue promotes which of the following characteristics?

<p>Critical thinking (B)</p> Signup and view all the answers

What is a key feature of the fake barn county problem?

<p>There are fake barns indistinguishable from real ones. (A)</p> Signup and view all the answers

Flashcards

Justified True Belief (JTB)

Plato's classic definition of knowledge, stating that knowledge is a true belief that is also justified.

Gettier Case

A situation where someone has a justified true belief, but it seems like they got lucky or didn't actually understand the situation. It challenges the JTB definition of knowledge.

JTB + No False Lemmas

This account adds a condition to JTB, stipulating that the belief cannot be based on a false premise. It aims to address Gettier problems by preventing 'lucky' knowledge.

Reliabilism

A theory of knowledge valuing the reliability of the process by which knowledge is acquired. Reliable sources and processes generate knowledge.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Virtue Epistemology

Knowledge is the result of a virtuous mental process that adheres to certain intellectual standards, like good reasoning and appropriate evidence.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Infallibilism

Knowledge is based on beliefs that cannot be doubted, even if they are held with absolute certainty. Any possibility of error disqualifies it from being knowledge.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Knowledge How

Knowing how to do something. It's a skill or ability.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Knowledge Of

Knowing someone or something personally, including their qualities and characteristics.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Truth Condition

A philosophical concept that describes how you cannot know something false.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Belief Condition

A philosophical concept that describes how you cannot know something you don't believe.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Justification Condition

In the context of knowledge, justification refers to the reason or evidence that supports a belief.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Objective Truth

The idea that something is true or false regardless of what people believe.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Gettier Problem

A situation where a person's belief is true, but the justification for that belief is flawed or misleading.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Disjunction Introduction (Addition)

A logical rule that allows you to add a statement to a true statement, creating a new true statement.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Knowledge Without Belief

A philosophical argument that claims knowledge can exist even without conscious belief.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Alternative Definitions of Knowledge

Philosophical theories about knowledge that aim to address the problems raised by Gettier cases.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Empiricism

The belief that knowledge is based on perception and sensory experience.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Rationalism

The belief that knowledge is based on reason and logic.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Fake Barn County

A scenario where someone is driving through a town full of fake barns, and only accidentally stumbles upon a real barn. This challenges JTB + No False Lemmas because the belief is justified, true, and not inferred from anything false, but doesn't feel like knowledge because of the context.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Zagzebski's Formula

A formula created by philosopher Linda Zagzebski to demonstrate how definitions of knowledge involving 'true belief + a third condition' are likely to fall victim to Gettier-style cases.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Justification

The condition of a belief being supported by adequate evidence or reasons. It's the foundation for justified true belief.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Belief

A mental state where you hold a belief, whether it's true or false. It's the first step in forming knowledge.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Truth

The concept of having beliefs that are true, making them accurate and consistent with reality. It's a crucial element of knowledge.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Inference

The process of drawing logical conclusions from existing information or beliefs. It's important for forming justified beliefs.

Signup and view all the flashcards

False Lemma

A false premise or assumption that is used as a basis for reasoning. It can lead to incorrect conclusions.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Reliable Method

The idea that true beliefs can be acquired through reliable processes, like having good eyesight or using a trustworthy source.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Intellectual Virtues

A person's traits or characteristics that promote intellectual excellence and the pursuit of knowledge, like rationality, critical thinking, and open-mindedness.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Apt Belief

A belief that is accurate and true because the believer used their intellectual virtues.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Zagzebski's Virtue Epistemology

The belief that knowledge is based on intellectual virtues, like a skilled archer aiming accurately with a good bow. It connects truth with the process, ruling out lucky knowledge.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Gap Between Truth and Other Conditions

The gap that exists when truth and other conditions of knowledge, like justification, are simply added together without a strong link. This allows for lucky cases to be misclassified as knowledge.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Zagzebski's Argument Against JTB + Third Condition

This argument against definitions of knowledge as JTB + a third condition. It states that any such definition can be defeated by a lucky case where truth and the third condition are not truly linked.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Act of Moral Virtue

An act where the actor both intends to do good and successfully achieves that goal. Good intentions without results, or successful actions with poor intentions, do not qualify as virtuous.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Intellectual Virtue and Knowledge

Knowledge is obtained through intellectual virtues, like good reasoning and seeking evidence. This process must lead to true beliefs, like a virtuous archer making an accurate shot.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Problem: Children and Animals

A criticism of virtue epistemology that argues it may wrongly exclude children or animals from possessing knowledge, even though they can seem to know things.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Problem: Too Strict

A criticism of Infallibilism - It sets the bar for knowledge too high, making it nearly impossible to know anything, even established facts.

Signup and view all the flashcards

Study Notes

Overview – The Definition of Knowledge

The definition of knowledge is one of the oldest questions of philosophy. Plato’s answer, that knowledge is justified true belief, stood for thousands of years – until a 1963 philosophy paper by philosopher Edmund Gettier challenged this definition.

Gettier described two scenarios – now known as Gettier cases – where an individual has a justified true belief but that is not knowledge.

Since Gettier’s challenge to the justified true belief definition, various alternative accounts of knowledge have been proposed. The goal of these accounts is to define ‘knowledge’ in a way that rules out Gettier cases whilst still capturing all instances of what we consider to be knowledge.

A Level philosophy looks at 5 definitions of knowledge:

  • Justified true belief (the tripartite definition)
  • JTB + No false lemmas
  • Reliabilism
  • Virtue epistemology
  • Infallibilism

It’s important to first distinguish the kind of knowledge we’re discussing here. Broadly, there are three kinds of knowledge:

  • Ability: knowledge how e.g. “I know how to ride a bike”
  • Acquaintance: knowledge of – e.g. “I know Fred well”
  • Propositional: knowledge that – e.g. “I know that London is the capital of England”

When we talk about the definition of knowledge, we are talking about the definition of propositional knowledge specifically.


Justified True Belief


The tripartite definition

In Theaetetus, Plato argues that knowledge is “true belief accompanied by a rational account”. This got simplified to:

  • Justified
  • True
  • Belief

‘Justified true belief’ is known as the tripartite definition of knowledge.

Necessary and sufficient conditions

The name of the game in defining ‘knowledge’ is to provide necessary and sufficient conditions.

The two circles overlap perfectly because ‘unmarried man’ is a perfect definition of ‘bachelor’

For example, ‘unmarried’ and ‘man’ are both necessary to be a ‘bachelor’ because if you don’t meet both these conditions you’re not a bachelor. Further, being an ‘unmarried man’ is sufficient to be a ‘bachelor’ because everything that meets these conditions is a bachelor. So, ‘unmarried man’ is a good definition of ‘bachelor’ because it provides both the necessary and sufficient conditions of that term.

The correct definition of ‘knowledge’ will work the same way. Firstly, we can argue that ‘justified’, ‘true’, and ‘belief’ are all necessary for knowledge.

For example, you can’t know something if it isn’t true. If someone said, “I know that the moon is made of green cheese” you wouldn’t consider that knowledge because it isn’t true.

Similarly, you can’t know something you don’t believe. It just wouldn’t make sense, for example, to say “I know today is Monday but I don’t believe today is Monday.”

And finally, justification. Suppose someone asks you if you know how many moons Pluto has. You have no interest in astronomy but just have a strong feeling about the number 5 because it’s your lucky number or whatever. You’d be right – Pluto does indeed have 5 moons – but it seems a bit of a stretch to say you knew Pluto has 5 moons. Your true belief “Pluto has 5 moons” is not properly justified and so would not count as knowledge.

So, ‘justified’, ‘true’, and ‘belief’ may each be necessary for knowledge. But are these conditions sufficient? If ‘justified true belief’ is also a sufficient definition of knowledge, then everything that is a justified true belief will be knowledge. However, this is challenged by Gettier cases.

Problem: Gettier cases

Gettier’s paper describes two scenarios where an individual has a justified true belief that is not knowledge. Both scenarios describe a belief that fails to count as knowledge because the justified belief is only true as a result of luck.

Gettier case 1

  • Smith and Jones are interviewing for the same job
  • Smith hears the interviewer say “I’m going to give Jones the job”
  • Smith also sees Jones count 10 coins from his pocket
  • Smith thus forms the belief that “the man who will get the job has 10 coins in his pocket”
  • But Smith gets the job, not Jones
  • Then Smith looks in his pocket and, by coincidence, he also has 10 coins in his pocket

Smith’s belief “the man who will get the job has 10 coins in his pocket” is:

  • Justified: he hears the interviewer say Jones will get the job and he sees that Jones has 10 coins in his pocket
  • True: the man who gets the job (Smith) does indeed have 10 coins in his pocket

But despite being a justified true belief, we do not want to say that Smith’s belief counts as knowledge because it’s just luck that led to him being correct.

This shows that the tripartite definition of knowledge is not sufficient: you can have a justified true belief that is not knowledge.

Gettier case 2

Gettier’s second example relies on the logical principle of disjunction introduction (or, more simply, addition).

Disjunction introduction says that if you have a true statement and add “or some other statement” then the full statement (i.e. “true statement or some other statement”) is also true.

For example: “London is the capital of England” is true. And so the statement “either London is the capital of England or the moon is made of green cheese” is also true, because London is the capital of England. Even though the second part (“the moon is made of green cheese”) is false, the overall statement is true because the or means only one part has to be true (in this case “London is the capital of England”).

Gettier’s second example is as follows:

  • Smith has a justified belief that “Jones owns a Ford”
  • So, using the principle of disjunctive introduction above, Smith can form the further justified belief that “Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona”
  • Smith thinks his belief that “Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona” is true because the first condition is true (i.e. that Jones owns a Ford)
  • But it turns out that Jones does not own a Ford
  • However, by sheer coincidence, Brown is in Barcelona

So, Smith’s belief that “Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona”  is:

  • True: “Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona” turns out to be true. But Smith thought it was true because of the first condition (Jones owns a Ford) whereas it turns out it is true because of the second condition (Brown is in Barcelona)
  • Justified: The original belief “Jones owns a Ford” is justified, and so disjunction introduction means that the second belief “Either Jones owns a Ford or Brown is in Barcelona” is also justified.

But despite being a justified true belief, it is wrong to say that Smith’s belief counts as knowledge, because it was just luck that led to him being correct.

This again shows that the tripartite definition of knowledge is not sufficient.

Problem: Not necessary

The majority of this debate focuses on whether the tripartite definition is sufficient for knowledge, but you can potentially argue that one or more of the conditions are not necessary:

  • Justification: The fact that children and animals appear to possess knowledge suggests that justification is not necessary for knowledge because children and animals have knowledge even though they can’t justify it.
  • Truth: Zagzebski’s definition of knowledge does not explicitly include true as a condition but instead talks about acts of intellectual virtue (which kind of implies truth but anyway). Some philosophers reject the very idea of objective truth, but that’s getting a bit off-piste.
  • Belief: You can potentially imagine scenarios where someone knows something but doesn’t believe it. For example, you may have heard years ago that Pluto has 5 moons but forgotten it consciously. But when asked years later “how many moons does Pluto have?” you correctly answer “5” – even though you’re not sure about this answer and don’t really believe it.

Alternative definitions of knowledge


For an example essay plan on definitions of knowledge, see the How to Get an A in A-level Philosophy book

Gettier cases are a devastating problem for the tripartite definition of knowledge.

In response, philosophers have tried to come up with new definitions of knowledge that avoid Gettier cases.

Generally, these new definitions seek to refine the justification condition of the tripartite definition. True and belief remain unchanged.

JTB + no false lemmas

The no false lemmas definition of knowledge aims to strengthen the justification condition of the tripartite definition.

It says that James has knowledge of P if:

  • P is true
  • James believes that P
  • James’s belief is justified
  • James did not infer that P from anything false

So, basically, it adds an extra condition to the tripartite definition. It says knowledge is justified true belief + that is not inferred from anything false (a false lemma).

This avoids the problems of Gettier cases because Smith’s belief “the man who will get the job has 10 coins in his pocket” is inferred from the false lemma “Jones will get the job”.

Remember:

  • The tripartite definition says Smith’s belief is knowledge, even though it isn’t
  • The no false lemmas response says Smith’s belief is not knowledge, which is correct.

So, in this instance, the no false lemmas definition appears to be a more accurate account of knowledge than the tripartite view: it avoids saying Gettier cases count as knowledge.

Problem: fake barn county

However, the no false lemmas definition of knowledge faces a similar problem: the fake barn county situation:

Venn diagram highlighting the problems with the JTB and JTB+N definitions. JTB+N is an improvement on JTB, but the fake barn county example shows that this definition still includes cases that are not knowledge.

  • In ‘fake barn county’, the locals create fake barns that look identical to real barns
  • Henry is driving through fake barn county, but he doesn’t know the locals do this
  • Henry often thinks “there’s a barn” when he looks at the fake barns
    • These beliefs are not knowledge, because they are not true – the barns are fake
  • However, on one occasion Henry looks at the one real barn and thinks “there’s a barn”
    • This time the belief is true
    • It’s also justified by his visual perception of the barn
    • And it’s not inferred from anything false.

According to the no false lemmas definition, Henry’s belief is knowledge.

But this shows that the no false lemmas definition must be false. Henry’s belief is clearly not knowledge – he’s just lucky in this instance.

Reliabilism

Reliabilism says James knows that P if:

  • P is true
  • James believes that P
  • James’s belief that P is caused by a reliable method

A reliable method is one that produces a high percentage of true beliefs.

So, if you have good eyesight, it’s likely that your eyesight would constitute a reliable method of forming true beliefs. If you have an accurate memory, it’s likely your memory would also be a reliable method for forming true beliefs. If a website is consistent in reporting the truth, that website would also count as a reliable method.

But if you form a belief through an unreliable method – for example by simply guessing or using a biased source – then it would not count as knowledge even if the resultant belief is true.

Children and Animals

An advantage of reliabilism is that it allows for young children and animals to have knowledge. Typically, we attribute knowledge to young children and animals. For example, it seems perfectly sensible to say that a seagull knows where to find food or that a baby knows when its mother is speaking.

However, pretty much all the other definitions of knowledge considered here imply that animals and young children can not have knowledge. For example, a seagull or a baby can’t justify its beliefs and so justified true belief rules out seagulls and young babies from having knowledge. Similarly, if virtue epistemology is the correct definition, it is hard to see how a seagull or a newly born baby could possess intellectual virtues of care about forming true beliefs and thus possess knowledge.

However, both young children and animals are capable of forming beliefs via reliable processes, e.g. their eyesight, and so according to reliabilism are capable of possessing knowledge.

Problem: fake barn county

You can argue against reliabilism using the same fake barn county argument above: Henry’s true belief that “there’s a barn” is caused by a reliable process – his visual perception. Reliabilism would thus (incorrectly) say that Henry knows “there’s a barn” even though his belief is only true as a result of luck.

Virtue epistemology

There are several forms of virtue epistemology (we will look at two), but common to all virtue epistemology definitions of knowledge is a link between a belief and intellectual virtues. Intellectual virtues are somewhat analogous to the sort of moral virtues considered in Aristotle’s virtue theory in moral philosophy. However, instead of being concerned with moral good, intellectual virtues are about epistemic good. For example, an intellectually virtuous person would have traits such as being rational, caring about what’s true, and a good memory.

Linda Zagzebski: What is Knowledge?

Formula for creating Gettier-style cases

Philosopher Linda Zagzebski argues that definitions of knowledge of the kind we have looked at so far (i.e. ‘true belief + some third condition’) will always fall victim to Gettier-style cases. She provides a formula for constructing such Gettier cases to defeat these definitions:

  • Start with a situation where there is a belief that fits the definition (‘true belief + some third condition’) but is false due to bad luck
    • E.g. Henry’s belief “there’s a barn” when he is looking at the fake barns
  • Then change the situation to one where the belief fits that definition (‘true belief + some third condition’) but is true due to good luck
    • E.g. Henry’s belief “there’s a barn” when he is looking at the one real barn
  • In the second case, the belief will still fit the definition (‘true belief + some third condition’) because it’s basically the same as the first case
  • But the second case won’t be knowledge, because it’s only true due to luck

Zagzebski argues that this formula will always provide a means to defeat any definition of knowledge that takes the form ‘true belief + some third condition’ (whether that third condition is justification, formed by a reliable process, or whatever).

The reason for this is that truth and the third condition are simply added together, but not linked (the belief is not apt, to use Sosa’s terminology). The fact that truth and the third condition are not linked leaves a gap where lucky cases can incorrectly fit the definition.

Zagzebski’s definition of knowledge

The issues resulting from the gap between truth and the third condition motivate Zagzebski to do away with the ‘truth’ condition altogether. Instead, Zagzebski’s analysis of knowledge is that James knows that P if:

  • James believes that P
  • James’s belief that P arises from an act of intellectual virtue

However, in Zagzebski’s analysis of knowledge, the ‘truth’ of the belief is kind of implied by the idea of an act of intellectual virtues. This can be shown by drawing a comparison with moral virtue:

An act of moral virtue is one where the actor both intends to do good and achieves that goal. For example, intending to help an old lady across the road but killing her in the process is not an act of moral virtue because it doesn’t achieve a virtuous goal (despite the virtuous intent). Likewise, helping the old lady across the road because you think she will give you money is not an act of moral virtue – even though it succeeds in achieving a virtuous goal – because your intentions aren’t good.

Intellectual virtue is similar: You must both have the correct motivation (e.g. you want to find the truth) and succeed as a result of that virtue (i.e. your belief turns out to be true because you acted virtuously).

Virtues motivate us to pursue what is good. In the case of knowledge, good knowledge is also true. Secondly, virtues enable us to achieve our goals (in the same way a virtuous i.e. good knife enables you to cut) and so intellectual virtues would enable you to reliably form true beliefs.

Sosa’s virtue epistemology

Another virtue epistemology approach to knowledge is Ernest Sosa’s definition of apt belief.

Sosa uses the following analogy to argue that knowledge, like a virtuous shot in archery, has the following three properties: Accuracy, adroitness, and aptness.

ArcheryKnowledgeAccuracyThe arrow hits the target.The belief is true.AdroitnessThe archer is skilled.The believer is intellectually virtuous.AptnessThe arrow hits the target because of the archer’s skill, not just luck.The belief is true because of the believer’s intellectual virtues.

This last condition – aptness – differentiates Sosa’s understanding of knowledge from those criticised by Zagzebski above. According to Sosa, for something to qualify as knowledge the belief must be true as a direct consequence of the believer exercising their intellectual virtues – it must be apt. Aptness provides a link between truth and the third condition that rules out Gettier-style situations where the belief is only true as a result of luck.

Returning to the fake barn county example, Sosa’s virtue epistemology could (correctly) say Henry’s belief “there’s a barn” in fake barn county would not qualify as knowledge – despite being true and formed by a reliable method – because it is not apt. Yes, Henry’s belief is accurate (i.e. true) and adroit (i.e. Henry has good eyesight etc.), but he only formed the true belief as a result of luck, not because he used his intellectual virtues.

Problem: children and animals

As mentioned in more detail in the reliabilism section above, a potential criticism of virtue epistemology is that it appears to rule out the possibility of young children or babies possessing knowledge, despite the fact that they arguably can know many things.

Infallibilism

Infallibilism argues that for a belief to count as knowledge, it must be true and justified in such a way as to make it certain.

So, even though Smith has good reasons for his beliefs in the Gettier case, they’re not good enough to provide certainty. Certainty, to philosophers like Descartes, means the impossibility of doubt.

In the Gettier case, Smith might have misheard the interviewer say he was going to give Jones the job. Or, even more extreme, Smith might be a brain in a vat and Jones may not even exist! Either of these scenarios – however unlikely – raise the possibility of doubt.

Problem: too strict

So, infallibilism correctly says Smith’s belief in the Gettier case does not count as knowledge.

But it also says pretty much everything fails to qualify as knowledge!

*“I know that water boils at 100°*c” – can this be doubted? Of course it can! Your science teachers might have been lying to you, you might have misread your thermometer, you might be a brain in a vat and there’s no such thing as water!

Pretty much any belief can be doubted, as Descartes demonstrates in his three waves of doubt.

So, whereas Gettier cases show the tripartite definition to set the bar too low for knowledge, infallibilism sets the bar way too high – barely anything can be known! In other words, we can argue that certainty is not a necessary condition of knowledge.

Studying That Suits You

Use AI to generate personalized quizzes and flashcards to suit your learning preferences.

Quiz Team

Description

Test your understanding of the tripartite definition of knowledge as outlined by Plato and the challenges raised by Gettier cases. This quiz explores various components and critiques of knowledge through philosophical inquiry. Dive into key concepts and alternative accounts in epistemology.

More Like This

Use Quizgecko on...
Browser
Browser