Document Details

Uploaded by Deleted User

Tim Dunne, Brian C. Schmidt

Tags

international relations realism political theory international politics

Summary

This document is a chapter from a book on international relations that examines the theory of realism. The chapter discusses the history and core concepts of realism, highlighting its focus on power, self-interest, and the state as a primary actor in the international system.

Full Transcript

Chapter 8 Realism tim dunne · brian c. schmidt Framing Questions Is there a timeless wisdom of realism? How do realists conceptualize world politics? Do all of the different theories of realism share a similar set of assumptions? Reader’s Guide...

Chapter 8 Realism tim dunne · brian c. schmidt Framing Questions Is there a timeless wisdom of realism? How do realists conceptualize world politics? Do all of the different theories of realism share a similar set of assumptions? Reader’s Guide section asks whether there is one realism or a variety of realisms. The argument presented is that despite Realism is the dominant theory of international rela- some important differences, all realist theories share tions. Why? Because it provides the most powerful a set of core assumptions and ideas. The third sec- explanation for the state of war that is the regular tion outlines these common elements, identified condition of life in the international system. This is as self-help, statism, and survival. The final section the bold claim that realists make in defence of their returns to the question of the extent to which real- tradition, a claim that this chapter critically examines. ism is relevant for understanding the globalization of After introducing the theory of realism, the second world politics. Chapter 8 Realism 131 Introduction The theory of realism has significantly influenced both new generation of realist writers who all emphasized the practice of world politics and the academic study the ubiquity of power and the competitive nature of of International Relations (IR). Many claim that before politics among nations. The standard account of the there was even a distinguishable subject matter of IR, Great Debate is that the realists emerged victorious, states’ diplomatic and military practices conformed and that idealism was relegated to the dustbin of his- to the principles that would later be identified as real- tory. Recently, however, a new body of revisionist his- ism. Some go so far as to argue that the power-seeking tory has challenged the story of the Great Debate by behaviour of human beings and their motives of fear, revealing that many of the realists completely misrep- honour, and profit illustrate the universality of realism. resented the inter-war scholars’ views (Schmidt 2012). The argument is that wherever and whenever groups of Robert Vitalis (2015) has suggested that by viewing people have sought to survive and perpetuate their own this period in terms of a debate between idealists and political communities, they have had no choice but to realists, the roles of race, imperialism, and empire pursue power and engage in struggle to defend them- have been erased from the field’s early development. selves. The claim that realism possesses a timeless qual- Other disciplinary historians have noted that by retro- ity is based on such arguments. Although often deeply spectively constructing an ‘idealist tradition’, the real- pessimistic, realists profess to describe the world the ists produced a caricature of several quite diverse (left, way it really is rather than how we wish it to be. liberal, feminist) political and intellectual movements At the conclusion of the Second World War, a new in the inter-war period (Wilson 1998). Yet, given the group of self-identified realist scholars rose to promi- context of rising tensions between the Soviet Union nence in the emergent field of IR. Many were German and the United States immediately after the Second émigrés who fled Europe and sought refuge in the World War, the realists argued that idealism had to United States. These scholars were highly critical of the be banished from the policy-making process. Realists approach taken by those writing and teaching during argued that the United States had to act on the basis of the inter-war period, whom they dubbed ‘idealists’ and its core national interests, rather than on the basis ‘utopians’. These realists argued that idealists’ search of abstract universal interests. With the dawn of the to find a cure for the disease of war resulted in their nuclear age, the core national interest of state survival ignoring the role of power; overestimating the degree could no longer be taken for granted. Realism taught to which nation-states shared a set of common inter- foreign policy officials to focus on interests rather ests; and being overly optimistic that rational solutions than on ideology, to seek peace through strength, and could be found to settle disputes peacefully. The out- to recognize that great powers can coexist even if they break of the Second World War in 1939 confirmed, for have antithetical values and beliefs. The fact that real- the realists at least, the inadequacies of the idealists’ ism offers something of a ‘manual’ for decision-mak- approach to studying international politics. ers looking to maximize the interests of their state A new approach, one based on the timeless insights in a hostile environment helps explain why it gained of realism, replaced the discredited idealist approach. such popularity in the late 1940s and 1950s, and why it Histories of IR describe a Great Debate that took place remains the dominant tradition in the study of world in the 1940s between the inter-war idealists and a politics. Realism in context The development of realism after the Second World War are commonly portrayed as belonging to an ancient is often claimed to rest on an older tradition of realist tradition of thought that includes such illustrious fig- thought. For the realists, tradition connects seminal ures as Thucydides (c.460–406 bc), Niccolò Machiavelli texts with context. In other words, it is important to (1469–1527), Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679), and Jean- understand the political circumstances in which vari- Jacques Rousseau (1712–78) (see Table 8.1). Despite the ous realist thinkers were living. Contemporary realists different time periods and political contexts in which 132 tim dunne · brian c. schmidt Table 8.1 The realist tradition Thinker Key text Big idea Context Thucydides History of the International politics is driven by an endless Greek city-state Peloponnesian War struggle for power, which has its roots in system human nature. Justice, law, and society either have no place or are circumscribed. Machiavelli The Prince Political realism recognizes that principles Italian are subordinated to policies; the ultimate city-states skill of a state leader is to accept and adapt to changing political and power configurations in world politics. Hobbes Leviathan Human beings have an insatiable lust for English civil war power. Life in the state of nature, which is similar to the condition of world politics, is full of fear and worry about violent death. Rousseau The State of War It is not human nature but the anarchical European state system that fosters fear, jealousy, suspicion, system and insecurity. these theorists wrote, their place in the realist tradition realism. There is, however, one issue in particular that is based on their shared recognition that international theorists associated with raison d’état, and realism politics is a continuous struggle for power. Those in the more generally, were concerned with: the role, if any, realist tradition contend that the condition of interna- that morals and ethics play in international politics. tional politics is analogous to a state of war in which Realists are sceptical of the idea that universal political actors have little choice but to be concerned moral principles exist, and therefore warn state leaders with their own security. The ever present possibility of against sacrificing their own self-interests in order to war necessitates that political actors take appropriate adhere to some indeterminate notion of ‘ethical’ con- measures, including the use of lethal force, to ensure duct. Moreover, realists argue that the need for survival their own survival. requires state leaders to distance themselves from tra- The insights these political theorists offered into the ditional notions of morality. Machiavelli argued that way in which state leaders should conduct themselves these principles were positively harmful if adhered to in the realm of international politics are often grouped by state leaders. It was imperative that state leaders under the doctrine of raison d’état, or reason of state. learned a different kind of morality, which accorded According to the historian Friedrich Meinecke (1957: 1), not with traditional Christian virtues but with politi- raison d’état is the fundamental principle of interna- cal necessity and prudence. Proponents of raison d’état tional conduct, the state’s First Law of Motion: ‘It tells often speak of a dual moral standard: one moral stan- the statesman what he must do to preserve the health dard for individual citizens living inside the state and a and strength of the State.’ Most importantly, the state, different standard for the state in its external relations which is identified as the key actor in international pol- with other states. But before one reaches the conclusion itics, must pursue power, and it is the duty of the states- that realism is completely immoral, it is important to person to calculate rationally the most appropriate add that proponents of raison d’état argue that the state steps that should be taken to perpetuate the life of the itself represents a moral force, for it is the existence of state in a hostile and threatening environment. The sur- the state that creates the possibility for an ethical politi- vival of the state can never be guaranteed, because the cal community to exist domestically. use of force culminating in war is a legitimate instru- Some in the realist tradition attribute the war-like ment of statecraft. As discussed later in this chapter, the condition of international politics to certain propen- assumption that the state is the principal actor, coupled sities found in human nature, while others emphasize with the view that the environment that states inhabit the unique environment in which international poli- is a perilous place, helps to define the essential core of tics takes place. Still others combine these two levels Chapter 8 Realism 133 of analysis—human nature and the environment or that world politics is analogous to the life of human structure of international politics—to account for the beings in a hypothetical state of nature was developed state of war. Machiavelli’s moral scepticism derived further by Rousseau. Although Rousseau was critical from his analysis of human nature as well as from the of how Hobbes depicted human nature, he too recog- observations he made while serving as a public official nized the necessity of human beings leaving the state of of the Florentine Republic. To be successful in politics, nature and forming a social contract. Unlike Hobbes, Machiavelli argued, one had to act on the basis of what however, Rousseau was deeply concerned that the con- human nature is really like, not how one wishes it to tract establishing sovereignty should reflect the general be. In his writings, Machiavelli provided a cynical and will of the people; he argued that this was the only way pessimistic description of human nature. In The Prince, in which the exercise of authority could be deemed Machiavelli wrote that men ‘are ungrateful, fickle, sim- legitimate. The problem, however, was that even if the ulators and deceivers, avoiders of danger, greedy for newly formed contract embodied the general will of its gain’ (Bondanella and Musa 1979: 131). Based on this members, each state merely articulates a particular will account of human nature, Machiavelli provided a set vis-à-vis other states. In other words, while the forma- of ‘realist’ maxims such as: it is better to be feared than tion of a social contract solves one set of problems, it loved; a prince should act like both a lion and a fox; and creates another set of problems for international rela- it is sometimes necessary to learn how not to be good. tions: namely, no higher power exists to help settle con- According to Machiavelli, the necessities of politics, flicts among independent sovereign states. Rousseau’s such as the need to ensure the survival of the state by insights are important for neorealists, who emphasize any means, were derived from human nature. anarchy and the lack of central authority, rather than Hobbes’s place in the realist tradition is often said human nature, to explain international conflict. to rest on his description of human nature in a hypo- Thucydides holds a prominent place in the realist thetical state-of-nature condition. Like Machiavelli, tradition because his insights, in many ways, help to Hobbes’s account of human nature was deeply pessi- define the essence of realism. Thucydides was both an mistic. Some have argued that Hobbes’s pessimism and active participant in, and observer of, the Peloponnesian profound sense of fear resulted from the fact that he War, a conflict between Athens and Sparta, two great was writing during the tumultuous English Civil War powers in the ancient Greek world. Subsequent genera- and that his own premature birth coincided with the tions of realists have admired Thucydides’ work for the threat posed by the Spanish Armada. While Hobbes’s insights he raised about many of the perennial issues account of human nature incorporates a number of of world politics. The classical realist lineage begins characteristics, perhaps most important is his claim with Thucydides’ representation of power politics as a that all men have a restless desire for power that ceases law of human behaviour. The desire for power and the only in death. In the state of nature, where there is no need to follow self-interest are held to be fundamental higher authority to provide security, Hobbes argues aspects of human nature. The behaviour of the state as that the condition resembles a state of war of every man a self-seeking egoist is understood to be a reflection of against every man. The constant fear of violent death the characteristics of human beings. It is human nature in the state of nature leads Hobbes to conclude that the and the motivations of fear, honour, and self-interest life of man is ‘solitary, poore, nasty, brutish, and short’ that explain why international politics is necessarily (Hobbes 1985 : 186). power politics. Although Hobbes acknowledges that a state of At the same time, while Thucydides offered pro- nature has never truly existed, he suggests that the found insights about human nature, he was equally condition of international politics closely resembles cognizant of the international environment’s impact a state of war. In an important passage of Hobbes’s on the behaviour of states. Thucydides’ explanation of Leviathan (1651), he writes: ‘though there had never the underlying cause of the Peloponnesian War was been any time, wherein particular men were in a con- ‘the growth of Athenian power and the fear which this dition of warre one against another; yet in all times, caused in Sparta’ (Thucydides 1972 : 1.23). This Kings, and Persons of Soveraigne authority, because is considered to be a classic example of the impact that of their independency, are in continuall jealousies, and the distribution of power has on the behaviour of state in the state and posture of Gladiators;... which is a actors. Thucydides emphasizes that Sparta’s national posture of War’ (Hobbes 1985 : 188). The claim interest, like that of all states, was survival, and the 134 tim dunne · brian c. schmidt changing distribution of power represented a direct did demonstrate that acting purely on the basis of threat to its existence. Sparta was, therefore, compelled power and self-interest without any consideration by necessity to go to war in order to forestall the threat of of moral and ethical principles frequently results being vanquished by Athens. Thucydides also makes it in self-­defeating policies. After all, as Thucydides clear that Athens felt equally compelled to pursue power showed, Athens suffered an epic defeat while attempt- in order to preserve the empire it had acquired. The ing to follow its self-interest. Nevertheless, the three Athenian leader, Pericles, claimed to be acting on the core elements that we identify with realism—statism, basis of the most fundamental of human motivations: survival, and self-help—are present in the work of ambition, fear, and self-interest (see Case Study 8.1). those who constitute the realist tradition, stretching While the thinkers discussed above are commonly from Thucydides to the present. grouped together in the realist tradition, despite the Realism identifies the group as the fundamental unit different contexts in which they were writing, it is of political analysis. When Thucydides and Machiavelli important to note that their ideas are open to rival were writing, the basic unit was the polis or city-state, interpretations (M. Williams 2005). Although often but realists consider that since the Peace of Westphalia considered to be the quintessential realist, Thucydides (1648), the sovereign state has been the principal actor Case Study 8.1 The Melian dialogue—realism and the preparation for war justice depends on the equality of power to compel and that in fact the strong do what they have the power to do and the weak accept what they have to accept. MELIANS: [...] you should not destroy a principle that is to the general good of all men—namely, that in the case of all who fall into danger there should be such a thing as fair play and just dealing [...] ATHENIANS: This is no fair fight, with honour on one side and shame on the other. It is rather a question of saving your lives and not resisting those who are far too strong for you. MELIANS: It is difficult [...] for us to oppose your power and for- tune [...] Nevertheless we trust that the gods will give us fortune as good as yours [...] ATHENIANS: Our opinion of the gods and our knowledge of © Oxford University Press men lead us to conclude that it is a general and necessary law of nature to rule whatever one can. This is not a law that we made The ‘Melian dialogue’, one of the most significant episodes of ourselves, nor were we the first to act upon it when it was made. the war between Athens and Sparta, illustrates several key realist We found it already in existence, and we shall leave it to exist principles. This case study reconstructs the dialogue between the forever among those who come after us. We are merely acting in Athenian leaders who arrived on the island of Melos to assert accordance with it, and we know that you or anybody else with their right of conquest over the islanders, and the response the same power as ours would be acting in precisely the same this provoked. In short, what the Athenians are asserting over way [...] You seem to forget that if one follows one’s self-interest the Melians is the logic of power politics. Because of their one wants to be safe, whereas the path of justice and honour vastly superior military force, they present a fait accompli to involves one in danger [...] This is the safe rule—to stand up to the Melians: either submit peacefully or be exterminated. The one’s equals, to behave with deference to one’s superiors, and to Melians, for their part, try to buck the logic of power politics, treat one’s inferiors with moderation. responding with arguments invoking justice, the gods, and their MELIANS: Our decision, Athenians, is just the same as it was at allies the Spartans. first. We are not prepared to give up in a short moment the lib- The following is a short excerpt from the dialogue (Thucydides erty which our city has enjoyed from its foundation for 700 years. 1972 : 401–7). Note that the symbol [...] indicates where ATHENIANS: [...] you seem to us [...] to see uncertainties as reali- words from the original text have been omitted. ties, simply because you would like them to be so. ATHENIANS: Then we on our side will use no fine phrases say- Question 1: Are the Athenians correct that might makes right? ing, for example, that we have a right to our empire because we defeated the Persians [...] you know as well as we do that, when Question 2: Whose arguments, the Athenians’ or Melians’, do you these matters are discussed by practical people, the standard of find to be the most persuasive? Chapter 8 Realism 135 in international politics. This is often referred to as the What options do states have to ensure their own state-centric assumption of realism. Statism is the term security? Consistent with the principle of self-help, if a given to the idea of the state as the legitimate representa- state feels threatened it should seek to augment its own tive of the collective will of the people. The legitimacy of power by increasing its military capabilities. However, the state is what enables it to exercise authority within this is not always possible. States have therefore pur- its domestic borders. Yet outside the boundaries of the sued other options, such as forming military alliances state, realists argue that a condition of anarchy exists. and initiating preventive wars with the aim of ensur- Anarchy means that international politics takes place in ing their own survival. The fact that all of these options an arena that has no overarching central authority above were discussed by Thucydides and continue to be rel- individual sovereign states. Thus, rather than necessarily evant today is what gives realism its timeless quality. denoting chaos and lawlessness, realists use the concept Despite all of the criticisms of realism, there is little of anarchy to emphasize the point that the international doubt that the collective wisdom of the realist tradition realm is distinguished by its lack of a central authority. is helpful in understanding some of the enduring pat- Under anarchy, the survival of the state cannot be terns of world politics. The question of realism’s resil- guaranteed. Realists correctly assume that all states ience touches on one of its central claims, namely that wish to perpetuate their existence. Looking back at his- it embodies laws of international politics that remain tory, however, realists note that the actions some states true across time (history) and space (geopolitics). Thus, have taken to ensure their survival has resulted in other while political contexts change, realists believe that the states losing their existence. This is partly explained world continues to operate according to the logic of by the power differentials that exist among states. realism. The conclusion of the chapter returns to this Intuitively, states with more power have a better chance question of whether realism does embody ‘timeless of surviving than states with less power. Power is cru- truths’ about politics. cial to the realist lexicon and has traditionally been defined narrowly in military strategic terms. Yet irre- spective of how much power a given state may possess, Key Points the core national interest of all states must be survival. Like the pursuit of power, the promotion of the national Realism has significantly influenced both the theory and practice of world politics. interest is, according to realists, an iron law of necessity. Self-help is the fundamental principle of state action Outside the academy, realism has a much longer history in the work of classical political theorists such as Thucydides, in an anarchical system. According to realism, each Machiavelli, Hobbes, and Rousseau. state actor is responsible for ensuring its own survival. The unifying theme around which all realist thinking converges is that states find themselves in the condition of Realists do not believe it is prudent for a state to entrust anarchy such that their security cannot be taken for its safety and survival to another actor or to an interna- granted. tional institution, such as the United Nations. Unlike in domestic politics, there is no emergency number that Statism, survival, and self-help are three core elements of the realist tradition. states can dial when they are in mortal danger. One realism, or many? The notion of a monolithic theory of realism is typically takes as its point of departure the so-called increasingly rejected by both proponents and crit- First Great Debate between idealism and realism; and ics of the realist tradition. The belief that there is not structural or neorealism (1979 onwards), which offi- one realism, but many, leads logically to a delineation cially entered the picture following the publication of different types of realism. The most simple dis- of Kenneth Waltz’s Theory of International Politics tinction is a form of periodization that differentiates (1979). But rather than opt for the neat but intellectu- realism into three historical periods: classical real- ally unsatisfactory system of historical periodization, ism (up to the twentieth century), which is frequently this chapter outlines a taxonomy of realisms. A sum- depicted as beginning with Thucydides’ history of the mary of the varieties of realism outlined here is con- Peloponnesian War; modern realism (1939–79), which tained in Table 8.2. 136 tim dunne · brian c. schmidt Table 8.2 Taxonomy of realisms Type of realism Key thinkers Key texts Big idea Context Twentieth-century Morgenthau Politics among Politics is governed by laws that are End of the Second classical realism (1948) Nations created by human nature. The World War, onset of (human nature) mechanism we use to understand the cold war international politics is the concept of interests, defined in terms of power. Structural realism/ Waltz (1979) Theory of Anarchy leads to a logic of self-help The cold war, end neorealism International in which states seek to maximize of the cold war Politics their security. Balances of power recurrently form. Mearsheimer Tragedy of Great The anarchical, self-help system Post-cold war (2001) Power Politics compels states to maximize their relative power positions as they can never be sure of other states’ intentions. Neoclassical Zakaria (1998) From Wealth to The systemic account of world Post-cold war realism Power politics provided by structural realism is incomplete. It needs to be supplemented with better accounts of unit-level variables such as how power is perceived, and how leadership is exercised. Twentieth-century classical realism opportunities to increase their own power. He claimed Many of those originally advocating realism after the that the goal of every state, as of every individual, was to Second World War were émigré scholars who fled Nazi maximize its power. Morgenthau identified three basic Germany and arrived in the United States where they patterns of the struggle for power among states—to keep sought positions at American universities. Hans J. power (status quo), to increase power (imperialism), and Morgenthau (1904–80), who spent the majority of his to demonstrate power (prestige)—which he argued were career at the University of Chicago, was undoubtedly all rooted in humankind’s lust for power. the most important of these realists. While ostensibly One of realism’s key concepts is interest defined in couching his realist theory in terms of objective laws, terms of power. In the realm of foreign policy, the most Morgenthau recognized that the study of politics was important interest is securing the physical survival of more of an art than a science. Nicolas Guilhot (2011) has the state. Beyond this core national interest, countries recently argued that the turn to theory by Morgenthau have an abundance of other interests, but what was cru- and other like-minded scholars should be viewed as a real- cial for Morgenthau and the other post-Second World ist gambit that was meant to limit the influence of behav- War realists was that the pursuit of any interest always iouralists who were championing a science of politics. had to be congruent with the power a state possessed. Trying to shed what he took to be his adopted country’s In this manner, the concept of the national interest idealist thinking, Morgenthau never tired of repeating imposed a measure of discipline on foreign policy offi- his main proposition that ‘international politics, like all cials to ensure that the interests they were pursuing politics, is a struggle for power’, and that ‘whatever the were consistent with the power they possessed relative ultimate aims of international politics, power is always to other states. It is sometimes wrongly assumed that the immediate aim’ (Morgenthau 1955 : 25). For the concept of the national interest is devoid of any Morgenthau, human nature provided the best expla- moral content. Morgenthau argued that choice between nation for how states behave. Like some of the realist the national interest and morals was a false choice. thinkers discussed in the previous section, Morgenthau Although he was sharply critical of the notion that states argued that human beings were hard-wired to pursue should act on the basis of so-called universal moral prin- power over others and were continually looking for ciples, Morgenthau recognized that the national interest Chapter 8 Realism 137 included a moral component that could only be realized distribution of power in the international system is through the medium of power. Morgenthau further rec- the key independent variable in understanding war ognized that there were fewer constraints on the struggle and peace, alliance politics, and the balance of power. for power among nations compared to domestic politics. Structural realists are interested in providing a rank- This is one of the reasons why he urged foreign policy ordering of states so that they can discern the number officials to maintain a balance of power. of great powers that exist at any particular point in Realists throughout the ages have considered a bal- time. The number of great powers, in turn, determines ance of power to be essential to preserving the liberty of the overall structure of the international system. For states. Although various meanings have been attributed example, during the cold war from 1945 to 1989, there to the concept of a balance of power, the most common were two great powers—the United States and the Soviet definition holds that if a state’s survival is threatened Union—that constituted a bipolar international system, by a hegemonic state or coalition of stronger states, it and since the end of the cold war most argue that the should join forces with other states, and they should international system has been unipolar (see Ch. 4). establish a formal alliance and seek to preserve their How does the relative distribution of power impact own independence by checking the power of the oppos- the behaviour of states? Waltz argues that states, espe- ing side. The balance of power is a mechanism that seeks cially the great powers, have to be concerned about the to ensure an equilibrium of power, so that no one state capabilities of other states. The possibility that any state or coalition of states is able to dominate all the others. may use force to advance its interests causes all states The cold war competition between the East and West, to worry about their survival. According to Waltz, as institutionalized through the formal alliance sys- power is a means to an end, the end being security. In tem of the Warsaw Pact and the North Atlantic Treaty a significant passage, Waltz writes: ‘because power is a Organization (NATO), provides a prominent example possibly useful means, sensible statesmen try to have of the balance of power mechanism in action (see Ch. 3). an appropriate amount of it’. He adds, ‘in crucial situa- tions, however, the ultimate concern of states is not for power but for security’ (Waltz 1989: 40). In other words, Structural realism/neorealism rather than being power maximizers, states are security In 1979, the publication of Kenneth Waltz’s Theory of maximizers according to neorealists. Waltz argues that International Politics established structural realism, power maximization often proves to be counter-pro- or neorealism, as a dominant theory of world politics. ductive because it triggers a counterbalancing coalition Writing in the context of the cold war, Waltz concurred of states. Like Morgenthau, Waltz firmly believed that that international politics is a struggle for power, but he balances of power recurrently form. did not attribute this to human nature. Instead, Waltz John Mearsheimer’s theory of offensive realism, argued that security competition, inter-state conflict, which is another variant of structural realism, provides and the difficulties of achieving international coopera- a different account of the power dynamics that oper- tion resulted from the structure of the international sys- ate in the anarchic international system. While sharing tem: namely, the lack of an overarching authority above many of neorealism’s basic assumptions, Mearsheimer sovereign states. Neorealists define the structure of the differs from Waltz when it comes to describing the international system in terms of three elements: organiz- behaviour of states. Most fundamentally, offensive ing principles, differentiation of units, and distribution realism argues that states are power maximizers in of capabilities. Waltz identifies two different organizing that they ‘understand that the best way to ensure their principles: anarchy, which corresponds to the decen- survival is to be the most powerful state in the system’ tralized realm of international politics; and hierarchy, (Mearsheimer 2001: 33). Under anarchy, Mearsheimer which is the basis of domestic order. He argues that the agrees that self-help is the basic principle of action, units of the international system are functionally simi- yet he argues that states can never be certain about lar sovereign states; hence unit-level variation, such as the intentions of other states. Consequently, he con- whether a state is a democracy or not, is inconsequential. cludes that all states are continuously searching for It is the third element, the distribution of capabilities opportunities to gain more power at the expense of across units, that is, according to Waltz, of fundamental other states. Indeed, the ideal position, although one importance to understanding outcomes in international that Mearsheimer argues is impossible to achieve, is politics. According to structural realists, the relative to be the global hegemon of the international system. 138 tim dunne · brian c. schmidt This has not, however, prevented states from trying to realists to remind us of their key distinction between sta- become the hegemon, which tragically leads to a world tus quo and revisionist states. Neoclassical realists argue where states are primed for offence, periodically result- that the fact that Germany was a revisionist state in the ing in inter-state war. 1930s, and has been a status quo state since the end of the Second World War, is of fundamental importance to understanding state behaviour in the international sys- Neoclassical realism tem. Not only do states differ in terms of their interests, While structural realists attribute the drivers of state but they also differ in terms of their abilities to extract behaviour to the anarchical international system, some resources from the societies they rule. Another interven- contemporary realists are sceptical of the notion that ing variable is state power; neoclassical realists argue that the distribution of power can sufficiently explain the states possess different capacities to translate the various behaviour of states. Since the end of the cold war, a elements of national power into state power. Thus, con- group of scholars have attempted to move beyond the trary to Waltz, all states cannot be treated as ‘like units’. parsimonious assumptions of structural realism by Given the varieties of realism that exist, it is hardly adding a number of individual- and domestic-level fac- surprising that the coherence of the realist tradition has tors into their explanations of world politics. While the been questioned. The answer to the question of ‘coher- relative distribution of power is recognized to be an ence’ is, of course, contingent on how strict the criteria important influence on the behaviour of states, so are are for judging the continuities that underpin a partic- factors such as the perceptions of state leaders, state– ular tradition. It is a mistake to understand traditions society relationships, and state identity. In attempting as a single stream of thought, handed down in a neatly to build a bridge between structural and unit-level fac- wrapped package from one generation to another. But tors, this group of scholars has been characterized by despite the different strands running through the tradi- Gideon Rose (1998) as ‘neoclassical realists’. According tion over time, there is a sense in which all realists share to Stephen Walt, the causal logic of neoclassical real- a common set of propositions. ism ‘places domestic politics as an intervening variable between the distribution of power and foreign policy behavior’ (Walt 2002: 211). Key Points One important intervening variable is leaders them- selves, namely how they perceive the distribution of There is a lack of consensus as to whether we can meaningfully speak about realism as a single coherent theory. power. There is no single objective account of the dis- tribution of power; rather, what matters is how state There are good reasons for delineating different types of realism. leaders derive an understanding of the distribution of power. While structural realists assume that all states Classical realists attribute power-seeking behaviour to human nature. have a similar set of interests, neoclassical realists such Structural realism divides into two camps: those who argue that states are security maximizers (neorealism), and those as Randall Schweller (1996) argue that historically this who argue that states are power maximizers (offensive has not been the case. He argues that, with respect to realism). Waltz, the assumption that all states have an interest in security results in realism exhibiting a profoundly sta- Neoclassical realists bring individual and unit variation back into the theory. tus quo basis. Schweller returns to the writings of earlier The essential realism Statism The previous paragraphs argued that realism is a theoret- For realists, the state is the main actor in international ically broad church, embracing a variety of thinkers and politics and sovereignty is its distinguishing trait. The texts. Despite the numerous denominations, this chapter meaning of the sovereign state is inextricably bound up argues that all realists subscribe to the following ‘three Ss’: with the use of force. Realists concur with Max Weber’s statism, survival, and self-help. The next three subsec- famous definition of the state as ‘the monopoly of the tions consider each of these elements in more detail. legitimate use of physical force within a given territory’ Chapter 8 Realism 139 (M. Smith 1986: 23). Within this territorial space, sov- a discount precisely because its currency, power, has ereignty means that the state has supreme author- remained under-theorized and inconsistently used. ity to make and enforce laws. This is the basis of the Simply asserting that states seek power provides no unwritten contract between individuals and the state. answer to multiple crucial questions. Why do states According to Hobbes, for example, we trade our liberty struggle for power? Surely power is a means to an end in return for a guarantee of security. Once security has rather than an end in itself? Is there not a difference been established, civil society can begin. between the mere possession of power and the ability Realist theory operates according to the assumption to change the behaviour of others? that, domestically, the problems of order and security are Structural realists have attempted to define the mean- largely solved. However, in the external relations among ing of power with more conceptual clarity. Waltz tries to independent sovereign states, insecurities, dangers, and overcome the problem by shifting the focus from power threats to the very existence of the state loom large. Realists to capabilities. He suggests that states’ capabilities can be attempt to explain this by pointing to the fact that the very ranked according to their strength in the following areas: condition for order and security—namely, the existence of ‘size of population and territory, resource endowment, a sovereign—is missing from the international realm. economic capability, military strength, political stability Realists claim that, in anarchy, states compete with and competence’ (Waltz 1979: 131). The difficulty here is other states for power and security. The nature of this that resource strength does not always lead to military competition is viewed in zero-sum terms; in other words, victory. For example, in the 1967 Six Day War between more for one actor means less for another. This competitive Israel and Egypt, Jordan, and Syria, the distribution of logic of power politics confounds agreement on universal resources clearly favoured the Arab coalition and yet the principles, apart from the principle of non-intervention supposedly weaker side annihilated its enemies’ forces in the internal affairs of other sovereign states. But even and seized their territory. The definition of power as capa- this principle, designed to facilitate coexistence, is not bilities is even less successful at explaining how states have accepted by realists, who argue that in practice non-inter- used economic leverage to achieve their goals. A more vention does not apply in relations between great powers sophisticated understanding of power would focus on the and their ‘near abroad’. As evidenced by the US-led wars ability of a state to control or influence its environment in in Afghanistan and Iraq, powerful states believe they are situations that are not necessarily conflictual. able to suspend the non-intervention principle on the An additional weakness of the realist treatment of grounds of national security and international order. power concerns its exclusive focus on state power. For Given that the state’s first move is to organize power realists, states are the only actors that really ‘count’. domestically, and the second is to accumulate power Transnational corporations, international organiza- internationally, it is important to consider in more depth tions, and ideologically driven terrorist networks such what realists mean by their ubiquitous fusion of poli- as the so-called Islamic State and Al Qaeda do not fig- tics with power. It is one thing to say that international ure very prominently in realists’ analysis of power. Yet politics is a struggle for power, but this merely begs the given the influence that non-state actors exercise in question of what realists mean by power. Realists make world politics today, many question the adequacy of two important points about the concept of power. First, realism’s state-centric assumption. power is a relational concept: one does not exercise power in a vacuum, but in relation to another entity. Survival Second, power is a relative concept: calculations need to be made not only about one’s own power capabilities, but The second principle that unites realists is the assertion also about the power that other state actors possess. Yet that, in world politics, all states have a vital interest in the task of accurately assessing the power of other states survival. Although realists disagree on whether the accu- is infinitely complex, and is often reduced to lumping a mulation of power is an end in itself, few would dissent number of factors together, such as gross national prod- from the argument that states’ ultimate concern is sur- uct (GNP), military spending, and population size. vival, which is held to be a precondition for attaining all A number of criticisms have been made about how other goals. However, as the previous section mentioned, realists define and measure power (Schmidt 2005), controversy among structural realists has arisen over the many of which are discussed in later chapters in this question of whether states are principally security maxi- book. Critics argue that realism has been purchased at mizers or power maximizers. Neorealists such as Waltz 140 tim dunne · brian c. schmidt argue that states have security as their principal interest security dilemmas exist ‘when the military preparations and therefore seek only the requisite amount of power to of one state create an unresolvable uncertainty in the ensure their own survival. According to this view, states mind of another as to whether those preparations are are profoundly defensive actors and will not seek greater for “defensive” purposes only (to enhance its security power if that means jeopardizing their own security. In in an uncertain world) or whether they are for offensive contrast, offensive realists such as Mearsheimer argue purposes (to change the status quo to its advantage)’ that the ultimate goal of all states is to achieve a hege- (Wheeler and Booth 1992: 30). This scenario suggests monic position in the international system. According that one state’s quest for security is often another state’s to this view, states always desire more power and, if the source of insecurity. States find it difficult to trust one opportunity arises, will seek to alter the existing distribu- another and are often suspicious of other states’ inten- tion of power in their favour. Moreover, offensive realists tions. Thus the military preparations of one state are point out that sometimes states bandwagon with, rather likely to be matched by those of neighbouring states. than balance against, dominant powers. The irony is that, at the end of the day, states often feel Machiavelli tried to make a ‘science’ out of his reflec- no more secure than before they undertook measures tions on the art of survival. He wrote The Prince with to enhance their own security. the explicit intention of codifying a set of maxims that In a self-help system, neorealists argue that the bal- would enable leaders to maintain the survival of their ance of power will emerge even in the absence of a con- states. Two related Machiavellian themes recur in the scious policy to maintain the balance. Waltz argues writings of modern realists, both of which derive from that balances of power result irrespective of the inten- the idea that the realm of international politics requires tions of any particular state. In an anarchic system different moral and political rules from those that apply populated by states that seek to perpetuate themselves, in domestic politics. The task of protecting the state at all alliances will be formed that seek to balance against the costs (even if this requires sacrificing one’s own citizens) power of threatening states. Classical realists, however, places a heavy burden on state leaders’ shoulders. In are more likely to emphasize the crucial role that state the words of Henry Kissinger, the academic realist who leaders and diplomats play in maintaining the balance became Secretary of State during the Nixon presidency, of power. In other words, the balance of power is not ‘a nation’s survival is its first and ultimate responsibility; natural or inevitable; it must be constructed. it cannot be compromised or put to risk’ (Kissinger 1977: Case Study 8.2 shows how the US sought to main- 204). State leaders’ guide must be an ethic of responsi- tain a balance of power between Egypt and Israel—a bility: the careful weighing of consequences and the real- policy that has been called into question by the trans- ization that individual acts of an immoral kind might formation that has been under way since 2010 when have to be performed for the greater good. For example, mass demonstrations in Tahrir Square brought an end think of the ways in which governments frequently sus- to President Mubarak’s 40-year rule over Egypt. pend the legal and political rights of ‘suspected terror- Realists and their critics have always debated the ists’ in view of the threat they pose to national security. balance of power system. This is especially the case today, as some critics argue that the unipolar position of the United States has made the balance of power Self-help inoperative (Brooks and Wohlforth 2008). The question In the international system, there is no higher author- of whether balance of power politics continues to be ity to counter the use of force. War is always a possibil- relevant in the contemporary globalized era is closely ity because there is nothing that can prevent a state from related to the debate about American hegemony (see using force against another state. Security can therefore Opposing Opinions 8.1). only be realized through self-help. Waltz explains that in It is questionable whether other countries are will- an anarchic structure, ‘self-help is necessarily the prin- ing to balance against the US, as neorealism would pre- ciple of action’ (Waltz 1979: 111). States must ultimately dict. Whether it is the contrived balance of the Concert rely on themselves to achieve security. But in the course of of Europe in the early nineteenth century or the more providing for one’s own security, the state in question will fortuitous balance of the cold war, balances of power automatically be fuelling the insecurity of other states. are broken—either through war or through peaceful The term given to this spiral of insecurity is the change—and new balances emerge. What the peren- security dilemma. According to Wheeler and Booth, nial collapsing of the balance of power demonstrates is Chapter 8 Realism 141 Case Study 8.2 Strategic partnerships with ‘friendly’ dictators as a fierce critic of President Jimmy Carter’s foreign policy. She castigated Carter for collaborating in the social revolutions in Iran and Nicaragua, which had the consequence of replacing ‘moder- ate autocrats’ who were friendly to American interests with ‘less friendly autocrats of an extremist persuasion’. Not grasping this distinction showed ‘a lack of realism’ and was the main failing of the Carter administration—according to Kirkpatrick (1979). In the case of Egypt, successive American administrations, from Reagan onwards, have operationalized this distinction between a ‘moderate friendly autocrat’ and an unfriendly revolutionary regime. President Mubarak profited from this policy, as did his clique of army generals, party apparatchiks, and military police. During the post-9/11 decade, when the US was looking for allies in the global war on terror, the Egyptian leadership showed itself Egyptian-Americans demand a new government in Egypt to be a valuable ally—not least in suppressing alleged jihadist ter- © Jim West / Alamy Stock Photo rorist groups in that country. Yet, by the time of the Arab Spring, the Egyptian people had come to despise Washington for collud- Unflinching American support for Israel has been one of the most ing with the hated dictator. This dynamic shows that Kirkpatrick’s remarkable features of the post-1945 world order. What shaped distinction between friendly and unfriendly tyrants might just be in this partnership was America’s empathy with a people who had the eye of the beholder: for the hundreds of thousands of Egyptians experienced genocide at the hands of the Nazis but who had gone who took to the streets and marched on Tahrir Square, the Mubarak on to build a democratic society in a region of authoritarian states. era was anything but friendly. It is too soon to tell whether the real- What is less well known is the strong support that successive US ist argument for aligning American foreign policy with unpopular governments have given to Egypt, particularly since the Israeli– dictators across the Middle East will prove costly in the long run as Egyptian peace treaty of 1979. In addition to providing material civil wars and social revolutions sweep away the old regional order. rewards for this ‘cold peace’, successive American administrations took the view that stability in the Middle East was more likely to Question 1: Do dictators really make good allies? be achieved by propping up a stable Egyptian dictatorship. The case for building and maintaining close ties with friendly Question 2: What are the implications for national security when dictators was made by Jeane J. Kirkpatrick, who rose to prominence potential enemies can unleash weapons of mass destruction? that states are at best able to mitigate the worst con- Waltz argues that the metaphor of the stag hunt provides sequences of the security dilemma but are not able to a basis for understanding the problem of coordinating the escape it. The reason for this terminal condition is the interests of the individual versus the interests of the com- absence of trust in international relations. mon good, and the pay-off between short-term interests Realists have illustrated the lack of trust among states and long-term interests. In the self-help system of inter- by reference to the parable of the ‘stag hunt’. In Man, the national politics, the logic of self-interest militates against State and War, Waltz revisits Rousseau’s parable: the provision of collective goods, such as ‘security’ or ‘free trade’. In the case of the latter, according to the theory of Assume that five men who have acquired a rudimentary comparative advantage, all states would be wealthier in ability to speak and to understand each other happen to a world that allowed free movement of goods and services come together at a time when all of them suffer from hun- across borders. But individual states, or groups of states ger. The hunger of each will be satisfied by the fifth part of like the European Union, can increase their wealth by pur- a stag, so they ‘agree’ to cooperate in a project to trap one. suing protectionist policies. Of course the logical outcome But also the hunger of any one of them will be satisfied by is that the remaining states become protectionist, interna- a hare, so, as a hare comes within reach, one of them grabs tional trade collapses, and a world recession reduces the it. The defector obtains the means of satisfying his hunger wealth of each state. Thus the question is not whether all but in doing so permits the stag to escape. His immediate will be better off through cooperation, but rather who is interest prevails over consideration for his fellows. likely to gain more than another. It is because of this con- cern with relative gains that realists argue that coopera- (Waltz 1959: 167–8) tion is difficult to achieve in a self-help system. 142 tim dunne · brian c. schmidt Opposing Opinions 8.1 US hegemony is durable For Against US power is unmatched. In terms of raw power capabilities, the US relative power is declining. The United States’ share of GDP United States continues to be unrivalled. The United States mili- is declining as a result of the rise of China and other emerging tarily outspends all other states, enjoys command of the com- market nations. China is now the world’s leading manufactur- mons, has the largest GDP, the best universities, and continues to ing nation and is predicted to overtake the United States as the be at the forefront of technological innovation. world’s largest economy by 2050 or earlier. Absence of balancing. There is no evidence that other states are Balancing is occurring. States such as China and Russia are challenging US hegemony by forming military alliances or engag- increasing their military capabilities (internal balancing) and taking ing in counterbalancing. In fact, most states continue to welcome actions that inhibit the exercise of US hegemony (soft balancing). American hegemony and are more worried about China’s power The inability of the United States to secure a UN Security Council than that of the United States. resolution prior to its invasion of Iraq is evidence that states are worried about the unilateral exercise of American power. Decline is not inevitable. The fact that previous hegemons, such as Great Britain, declined does not mean US hegemony will Decline is inevitable. No state in history has managed to main- inevitably come to an end. Proponents contend that the institu- tain its predominant position forever. Today the facts speak for tionalized, rule-based, and liberal character of American hegem- themselves: America’s relative power, especially its economic ony has widespread appeal, which diminishes the incentives to power, is declining while that of other states, specifically China, establish a new hegemonic order (Ikenberry 2011). The interna- is rising (Layne 2011). The international system is quickly shifting tional system will continue to be characterized by unipolarity. towards multipolarity. 1. Is there enough empirical and historical evidence to support the optimists’ opinion that US hegemony is durable? 2. Do you agree with the pessimists’ opinion that decline is inevitable and that current trends support the view that US hegemony is waning? 3. How is it possible for realist scholars to be on different sides of the debate about US hegemony? For advice on how to answer these questions, see the pointers www.oup.com/he/baylis8e Key Points Statism is a central assumption of realism. This involves two claims. First, the state is the pre-eminent actor in world Key criticism: are there no limits to what actions a state can take in the name of necessity? politics. Second, state sovereignty signifies the existence of an independent political community, one that has juridical Self-help: no other state or international institution can be relied on to guarantee a state’s survival. authority over its territory. Key criticism: statism is flawed on both empirical grounds Key criticism: self-help is not an inevitable consequence of the absence of a world government; it is a logic that (challenges to state power from ‘above’ and ‘below’) and states have selected. Moreover, there are examples where normative grounds (the inability of sovereign states to states have preferred collective security systems, or forms respond to collective global problems such as famine, of regional security communities, in preference to environmental degradation, and human rights abuses). self-help. Survival is the primary objective of all states; this is the supreme national interest to which all political leaders must adhere. Conclusion This chapter began by considering the repeated realist that the continuities in international relations are more claim that the pattern of international politics—wars important than the changes, but critics find this claim interrupted by periods characterized by the prepara- to be increasingly problematic in the present age of tion for future wars—has remained constant over the globalization (see Ch. 1). Recent critics such as John preceding 25 centuries. Realists have consistently held Hobson (2012) have challenged the alleged universalism Chapter 8 Realism 143 of realism on the grounds of a pervasive Eurocentric it was one of the foremost proponents of globalization. conception of world politics. But critics should recall The core values of globalization—liberalism, capitalism, that the death-knell of realism has been sounded a and consumerism—are exactly those espoused by the number of times already, only to see the resurgence of US. At a deeper cultural level, realists argue that moder- new forms of realism. Although the conclusion of the nity is not, as liberals hope, dissolving the boundaries of cold war caught many realists off guard, they, unlike difference among the peoples of the world. From classi- liberal scholars, did not predict that the post-cold war cal realists such as Rousseau to structural realists such era would necessarily be peaceful. While proponents as Waltz, realist thinkers have argued that interdepen- of globalization highlight new developments in world dence is as likely to breed ‘mutual vulnerability’ as peace politics, such as regional integration, global intercon- and prosperity. And while questioning the extent to nectedness, and the growth of transnational and non- which the world has become more interdependent in rel- state actors, especially terrorist organizations (see ative terms, realists insist that the state is not going to be Chs 23, 32, and 28), realists point out that we are eclipsed by global forces operating either below or above increasingly witnessing a return to great power politics the nation-state. Nationalism, realists have continuously as China and Russia continue to challenge the position reminded us, remains a potent force in world politics. of the United States. The United States, in turn, appears There are good reasons for thinking that the to recognize this, as President Trump has launched a twenty-first century will be a realist century. Despite trade war with China, withdrawn from a number of efforts to rekindle the idealist flame, Europe continues multilateral treaties on the grounds of protecting state to be as divided by different national interests as it is sovereignty, and taken measures to increase the mili- united by common goals. In the Middle East, the slow tary’s capabilities. The rise and fall of great powers is and painful process of regime change is generating deeply rooted in history, and many realists are con- significant instability across the region, as external cerned about how this dynamic will unfold in the com- powers fuel proxy wars to safeguard their own vital ing years (see Ch. 5). Trump’s nationalist rhetoric has interests. China continues to emerge as a serious eco- resulted in a great deal of trepidation among scholars nomic and strategic competitor to the US and, if cur- of all stripes about the durability of the liberal order rent trends continue, will eventually replace the US that has both underpinned so-called globalization and as the leading economic power. At that point, realism facilitated peace among the great powers. If the United leads us to predict that Western norms of individual States abandons the liberal order that it helped to create rights and responsibilities will be under threat. Rather after the Second World War, it is not clear what comes than transforming global politics in its own image, next. Will the globalization project continue unabated, as liberalism sought to do in the twentieth century, perhaps under the leadership of China, or will nativ- realism has the intellectual resources to assert itself ism and nationalism derail globalism (see Ch. 4)? as a defensive doctrine which recognizes that interna- Realists do not have to situate their theory of world tional relations is a realm of value conflicts, and that politics in opposition to globalization per se; rather, what responsible statecraft involves careful calibrations they offer is a very different conceptualization of the pro- of interests. Above all, realism demands that states’ cess. Given the preponderance of power that the US held leaders act prudently—a quality that has been in short at the end of the cold war, it should not be a surprise that supply in the early part of the twenty-first century. Questions 1. How does the Melian dialogue illustrate key realist concepts such as self-interest, the balance of power, alliances, capabilities, empires, and justice? 2. Do you think there is one realism, or many? 3. Do you know more about international relations now than an Athenian student did during the Peloponnesian War? 4. Do realists confuse a description of war and conflict for an explanation of why they occur? 5. Does the return of great power politics once again vindicate realism? 144 tim dunne · brian c. schmidt 6. How would a realist explain the 9/11 wars? 7. Will Western governments and their institutions (such as NATO) have to become more realist if the ideas associated with Western civilization are to survive in the twenty-first century? 8. What is at stake in the debate between defensive and offensive realism? 9. Is structural realism sufficient to account for the variation in states’ behaviour? 10. How can realism help us to understand the globalization of world politics? Test your knowledge and understanding further by trying this chapter’s Multiple Choice Questions www.oup.com/he/baylis8e Further Reading For a general survey of the realist tradition Smith, M. J. (1986), Realist Thought from Weber to Kissinger (Baton Rouge, LA: Louisiana State University Press). An excellent discussion of many of the seminal realist thinkers. Walt, S. M. (2002), ‘The Enduring Relevance of the Realist Tradition’, in I. Katznelson and H. V. Milner (eds), Political Science: The State of the Discipline (New York: W. W. Norton). An exposition of the realist tradition from one of its leading proponents. Twentieth-century classical realism Carr, E. H. (1939), The Twenty Years’ Crisis 1919–1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations (London: Macmillan). An important critique of liberal idealism. Morgenthau, H. J. (1948), Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace (New York: Alfred A. Knopf). A foundational text for the discipline of International Relations. Structural realism Keohane, R. O. (ed.) (1986), Neorealism and its Critics (New York: Columbia University Press). This collection of essays includes key chapters by Kenneth Waltz, an interesting defence of realism by Robert Gilpin, and powerful critiques by Richard Ashley, Robert Cox, and J. G. Ruggie. Mearsheimer, J. (2001), The Tragedy of Great Power Politics (New York: W. W. Norton). This is the definitive account of offensive realism. Waltz, K. (1979), Theory of International Politics (Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley). This is the exemplar for structural realism. Neoclassical realism Lobell, S. E., Ripsman, N. M., and Taliaferro, J. W. (eds) (2009), Neoclassical Realism, the State, and Foreign Policy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). A comprehensive survey of neoclassical realism. Rose, G. (1998), ‘Neoclassical Realism and Theories of Foreign Policy’, World Politics, 51(1): 144–72. An important review article that is credited with coining the term ‘neoclassical realism’. Zakaria, F. (1998), From Wealth to Power: The Unusual Origins of America’s World Role (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press). Puts forth Zakaria’s theory of state-centric realism. To find out more about theories of world politics follow the web links www.oup.com/he/ baylis8e

Use Quizgecko on...
Browser
Browser