How Can I Be a Better Person.docx

Document Details

RightStarlitSky

Uploaded by RightStarlitSky

Tyler Junior College

Tags

virtue ethics moral philosophy ethical systems philosophy

Full Transcript

**How Can I Be a Better Person? On Virtue Ethics** Douglas Giles This chapter explores a variety of approaches to the question of moral virtue and what it means to be a good person. It examines four ethical systems that revolve around the concept of virtue: Aristotle's virtue ethics, Aquinas's Chr...

**How Can I Be a Better Person? On Virtue Ethics** Douglas Giles This chapter explores a variety of approaches to the question of moral virtue and what it means to be a good person. It examines four ethical systems that revolve around the concept of virtue: Aristotle's virtue ethics, Aquinas's Christian version of Aristotelian virtue ethics, Buddhist virtue ethics, and Daoist and Confucian virtue ethics. Each will be presented as a different way of understanding what it might mean to live as a good person. For Aristotle, this is to be understood in terms of striving for the mean between extremes in the context of a well-ordered political community. For Aquinas, it is to be understood within the context of Christianity and natural law. For Buddhism, virtue is understood in terms of a life oriented toward the eightfold path that leads to the end of suffering. For Chinese philosophy, both Daoist and Confucian, virtue means being in harmony with the Cosmic Dao. What is Virtue Ethics? In philosophies of virtue ethics, rather than an emphasis on following rules, the emphasis is on developing oneself as a good person. It is not that following rules is not important; it is more the sense that being ethical means more than simply following the rules. For example, given an opportunity to donate to a charity, deontologists (see [Chapter 6](https://press.rebus.community/intro-to-phil-ethics/chapter/kantian-deontology/)) would consider whether there is an ethical rule that required them to donate. Utilitarians (see [Chapter 5](https://press.rebus.community/intro-to-phil-ethics/chapter/utilitarianism/)) would consider whether a donation would produce better consequences if they donated than if they did not. Virtue ethicists would consider whether donating is the kind of action that a virtuous person would do. Another example would be deciding whether to lie or tell the truth. Rather than focus on rules or consequences, virtue ethicists ask what kind of person do they want to be: honest or dishonest? Virtue ethicists place more importance on being a person who is honest, trustworthy, generous and other virtues that lead to a good life, and place less importance on one's ethical duty or obligations. A common theme among virtue ethicists is stressing the importance of cultivating ethical values in order to increase human happiness. Businesses today increasingly incorporate virtue ethics in their work culture, often having a "statement of values" guiding their operations. Because the right ethical action depends on the particularities of individual people and their particular situations, virtue ethics links goodness with wisdom because virtue is knowing *how* to make ethical decisions rather than knowing a list of general ethical rules that will not apply to every circumstance. Virtue ethicists tend to reject the view that ethical theory should provide a set of commands that dictate what we should do on all occasions. Instead, virtue ethicists advocate the cultivation of wisdom and character that people can use to internalize basic ethical principles from which they can determine the ethical course of action in particular situations. Virtue ethicists tend to see ethical principles as being inherent in the world and as being discoverable by means of rational reflection and disciplined living. The different forms of virtue ethics may or may not focus on God as the ultimate source of ethical principles. What unites the various forms of virtue ethics is the focus on moral education to cultivate moral wisdom, discernment, and character in the belief that ethical virtue will manifest in ethical actions. Aristotle on Excellence and Flourishing A statue of a person Description automatically generated[Photograph of Aristotle bust](https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Aristotle_Altemps_Inv8575.jpg) by [Jostrow](https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/User:Jastrow) via Wikimedia Commons. This work is in the public domain. The ancient Greek philosopher Aristotle (384-322 BCE) believed that to understand something we need to understand its nature and proper function (see [Chapter 2](https://press.rebus.community/intro-to-phil-ethics/chapter/can-we-have-ethics-without-religion-on-divine-command-theory-and-natural-law-theory/)). He also believed that everything has an end, or goal, toward which it naturally moves. For example, a seed grows into a tree because the purpose and function of the seed is to grow into a tree. Objects fulfill their purpose, not out of conscious desire, but because it is in their nature to fulfill their functions. Aristotle believed that our purpose is to pursue our proper human end, *eudaimonia***,** which is best understood as human flourishing or living well. *Eudaimonia* is not momentary pleasure but enduring contentment---not just a good day but a good life. Aristotle said that one swallow does not make a summer, and so, too, one day does not make one blessed and happy. It is human nature to move toward *eudaimonia* and this is the purpose, function, or final goal (*telos*) of all human activity. We work to make money, to make a home, and we sacrifice to improve our future, all with the ultimate aim of living well. Human flourishing means acting in ways that cause your essential human nature to achieve its most excellent form of expression. Aristotle held that a good life of lasting contentment can be gained only by a life of virtue---a life lived with both *phrónesis*, or "practical wisdom," and *aretē*, or "excellence." Aristotle defines human good as the activity of the soul in accordance with virtue, and wrote in the *Nicomachean Ethics *that we take the characteristic activity of a human being to be a certain kind of life; and if we take this kind of life to be activity of the soul and actions in accordance with reason, and the characteristic activity of the good person to be to carry this out well and nobly, and a characteristic activity to be accomplished well when it is accomplished in accordance with the appropriate virtue; then if this is so, the human good turns out to be activity of the soul in accordance with virtue. (1.7)[^\[1\]^](https://press.rebus.community/intro-to-phil-ethics/chapter/how-can-i-be-a-better-person-on-virtue-ethics/#footnote-107-1) The ethical demand on us is to develop our character to become a person of excellent ethical wisdom because, from that excellence, good actions will flow, leading to a good life. Virtuous actions come from a virtuous person; therefore, it is wise to focus on being a virtuous person. For Aristotle, ethics is a science with objective rational principles that can be discovered and understood through reason. Whether a particular course of action is good or not, and whether a person is good or not, are ideas that can be understood objectively. The cultivation of virtue must be accompanied by a cultivation of rationality. Aristotle saw the human soul as having three components: the nutritive part, responsible for taking in nutrition; the sensitive and appetitive part, responsible for sensing and responding to the environment, including the desires and appetites that motivate actions; and the rational part, responsible for practical and productive intellect. All three components are essential to being a human, but they exist in a clear hierarchy, with the faculties of reason at the top; these can and should control and guide the appetites into productive and ethical actions. Aristotle characterizes the desiring and emotional part of the soul as partaking of reason insofar as it complies with reason and accepts its leadership. The person of good virtue has cultivated a stable soul that is not swayed by appetites or desires but is governed by reason. Being ethical, then, is a skill that one develops. Just as you can through practice become good at math or playing a musical instrument, you can through practice become a virtuous person. When you have reached a certain level of skill in math or playing music, you no longer need a teacher to guide you, and you quickly can understand what to do. The same is true in Aristotle's conception of ethical decision making---it becomes an ingrained habit. How can the rational human come to understand what proper ethical actions are? Aristotle's answer is his doctrine of the mean, or the balanced course of action: Virtue is a state of character concerned with a choice, lying in a mean relative to us, this being determined by a rational principle, and by that principle by which the person of practical wisdom would determine it. (*Nicomachean Ethics* 2.6) We see here Aristotle's emphasis on a virtuous character that enables us to make a rational ethical choice. There are two important aspects of this. The first is the concept of the choice lying in a mean relative to our circumstances, and the second is that what the mean is in any particular situation can be determined by the person of practical reason. The ethical course of action is relative to our particular circumstances, meaning that there is not one rule that fits all situations, but the ethical course of action is objectively true in that any rational person looking at the situation will be able to understand the correct ethical course of action. By the mean, Aristotle refers to something midway between two extremes. The virtuous act is the one that falls between the extremes of what is deficient and what is excessive relative to the situation. All of the moral virtues are a mean between harmful extremes (too little, too much) in our actions and emotions: **Sample virtues as means between extremes** ---------------------------------------------- ------------------- -------------------- **Too Little** **Mean (Virtue)** **Too Much** Cowardice Bravery Foolhardiness Stinginess Generosity Profligacy Self-ridicule Confidence Boastfulness Apathy Calmness Short-Temperedness Sometimes the mean lies closer to one extreme than the other because of the particular circumstances involved. Because situations are different, it is not sufficient to say, "Be brave" because the mean of bravery differs from situation to situation. There are still ethical standards, but they are relative to the situation. It is always wrong to eat too much, but "too much" will be different for each individual. That is why an emphasis on virtue---the ability to discern *how* to make ethical decisions---is the key to an ethical, good, and balanced life that is worth living. The better you are at finding and acting on the mean, the more you have *phrónesis* ("practical wisdom"). This form of practical reason helps one recognize which features of a situation are morally relevant and how one can do the right thing in practice. Practical reason is rational because it is open to rational influence. Again, virtue is a learned skill. A person who listens to and learns from the reason of others is a rational person, and the same holds for ethics. As Aristotle sees it, every thought that one has, and action that one takes, contributes to the development of either a virtue or a vice. Virtues such as temperance, courage, and truthfulness become increasingly a part of our actions the more we intend to do them and the more we practice doing them. The truly virtuous person: - Knows what she or he is doing. - Chooses a virtuous act for its own sake. - Chooses as a result of a settled moral state. - Chooses gladly and easily. These are possible only through developing a virtuous disposition in which the soul is settled by reason. The more you practice virtue, the more you are capable of virtue because virtue becomes a way of life. Leading an objectively rational good life will produce a subjectively happy life of the kind appropriate to being human. Thomas Aquinas on Virtue ![A painting of a person with a book and a church Description automatically generated](media/image2.jpeg)[Saint Thomas Aquinas](https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:St-thomas-aquinas.jpg) by Carlo Crivelli via Wikimedia Commons. This work is in the Public Domain. Most of Aristotle's writings were lost to Western Europe up until the twelfth century. When Islam spread across Egypt, the Levant, and Persia in the seventh century, libraries of old Greek writings were found, including works of Aristotle lost to the Latin-speaking world. Ibn Sina (Avicenna), Ibn Rush (Averroës), and other Islamic thinkers recognized the value of Aristotle and wrote commentaries on his works and other works extending his philosophy. Those Islamic works were discovered by Christians when they conquered central Islamic Spain in the mid-twelfth century. Like their Islamic counterparts a few centuries earlier, Christian scholars knew what they had in the Islamic libraries. Works by Aristotle (who the Christian scholars knew from his logic books) were eagerly translated into Latin and distributed widely. Aristotle's texts posed problems for Christian philosophers in reconciling them with Christian theology, which led to many arguments within the thirteenth-century Catholic Church. Enter Thomas Aquinas (1225-1274), who wrote the *Summa Theologia* (The Sum of Theological Knowledge), creating a system that could, as advertised, provide answers to all questions. Aquinas's philosophy was based on the writings of Aristotle, who he reverently called "The Philosopher" and placed as a source of truth almost on the same level as the Bible. You will see similarities between Aristotle's and Aquinas's ethical systems. Like Aristotle, Aquinas based ethics on the pursuit of our proper human end. Unlike Aristotle, Aquinas believed that our proper human end of *eudaimonia* is not found in this world. Aristotle's system, Aquinas believed, was as good as humans could achieve on the basis of the natural realm, but our end as humans is to be perfected through union with God. For Aquinas, every event occurs because there is some end toward which things are directed, and we humans, like everything else in the universe, have our own ends. Unlike everything else, we as humans can consciously choose which ends we pursue, and ethics concerns which ends are worth our efforts to pursue. Like Aristotle, Aquinas believed that ethical understanding comes through virtue and that virtue is a skill that must be developed. Also like Aristotle, Aquinas believed that we learn what is ethical through our reason, which we can use to uncover God's natural law that is imbued in creation. By rationally reflecting on what is in accord with nature and our own natural inclinations, we can understand the ethical virtues. Aquinas's Aristotelian idea that humans can rationally understand ethical principles had to deal with the Christian concept that humanity's sinful nature prevented such understanding. He held that sin affects our moral life but not our rational life, clearing the way for the use of our human intellect to learn ethical truths. He borrowed from Islamic philosophers the conception that intellect is both passive and active. Intellect passively takes in sense experience and ideas but actively processes them to abstract universal truths. This is a natural process that is inherent in the human mind without requiring illumination from God and that is unaffected by sin (as was commonly taught in Aquinas's time). The universals abstracted by the mind from multiple individuals (e.g., "triangle" can be abstracted from individual triangles) are tied to real features in the world, the universals created by God and first existing in the mind of God, who used them to create the objects in the world. Put simply, we use our intellect to understand the world God has created. It is an orderly and purposeful world, with all of the objects in it receiving their purpose from God. By observing the world and reflecting on our observations, we can learn about the natural world, including God's ethical laws, which permeate the natural world. Aquinas used this conception to develop what we now know as "natural law"---the idea that ethical truths are ingrained in nature (see [Chapter 2](https://press.rebus.community/intro-to-phil-ethics/chapter/can-we-have-ethics-without-religion-on-divine-command-theory-and-natural-law-theory/) for more on Aquinas's view of natural law). To be virtuous, we need to learn God's natural law that governs the motion of objects in nature and instructs us in ethical behavior. To be rational, which is central to our human ends, requires intellectual discipline, but it is the way to virtue. Through self-discipline and reflecting on the natural law, we learn and develop as ingrained habits the four cardinal virtues of temperance, courage, prudence, and justice. Virtuous persons practice the four cardinal virtues in their daily lives, and from those virtues flow ethical behaviors in all situations. Buddhist Virtue Ethics Buddhism is a spiritual and philosophical tradition founded by Siddhārtha Gautama in India in the fifth century BCE. There are many schools of Buddhist thought in many countries, from monasteries devoted to religious ritual devotion to solitary practitioners of meditative practices. A common thread among most Buddhist schools of thought is an emphasis on a virtue ethical system that teaches the art of becoming balanced and harmonious through humility, with the goal of being free from *dukkha*, or suffering or anguish. We can free ourselves from suffering by extinguishing hatred and ignorance, following the teaching of the founder of Buddhism, Siddhārtha Gautama, who became "Buddha," which means "the Awakened One." Siddhartha Gautama taught that what could be called evil acts are performed out of ignorance and fear; therefore, rules and threats of punishment do not curtail these acts. We learn how to act in a suitable way (*sammā*, meaning best or most effective in the circumstances) by focusing on thinking suitably because our thoughts lead to our actions. The emphasis in Buddhism is on what is suitable and unsuitable rather than on the Western sense of right and wrong or good and evil. A life of virtue is outlined by the eightfold path: suitable view, intention, mindfulness, concentration, effort, speech, bodily conduct, and livelihood. By making one's thoughts and actions suitable, one promotes positive outcomes and lessens harmful outcomes. This is especially important to Buddhists because of the Gautama's teaching about karma, a concept that underlies Buddhist ethics and differs significantly from the divine command ethics found in many religions. The idea of karma is that it is a natural phenomenon that we can think of similarly to how we think of the laws of physics. The law of karma says that thoughts and actions that intend to harm others will eventually cause harm to ourselves and that thoughts and actions that intend to benefit others will eventually benefit us. In the Buddhist conception of time, "eventually" could mean in a future life that is multiple reincarnations away, so Buddhists think less in terms of immediate consequences of thoughts and actions and more in terms of the intrinsic value of them. Karma is not a strict determinism in that we still have free will and can mitigate the consequences of karma through our virtuous thoughts and actions. To avoid future suffering in this life or future lives, a Buddhist focuses on developing inner virtue to be able to think and act suitably in order to avoid negative karma, and to generate positive karma. As with Aristotle's virtue ethics, the more you practice virtue, the more you are capable of virtue. Having made a commitment to follow the eightfold path as a way of life, you are disposed to follow those rules. Chinese Virtue Ethics For more than two millennia, Chinese philosophy has been dominated by two great traditions, Confucianism and Daoism (Taoism), that have influenced China throughout its history and are important to Chinese culture still to this day. Both traditions are founded on their teaching of the *Dao*, which is best translated as "the way." Dao is both noun and verb, both how the universe is and how things behave properly. The Dao cannot be described completely in words but can be sensed as the source of all things and the rhythm of Being. All things come from Dao, and all things have their own Dao, or essence, which comes from the Cosmic Dao. Adepts of both Confucianism and Daoism believe that to be in the Dao and in harmony with it is to be virtuous and at peace, and that this state of enduring harmony with the Dao, similar to Aristotle's *eudaimonia*, is the proper human goal. Both Confucianist and Daoist ethical systems teach that a community flourishes when its members are in harmony with the Dao, and that the state flourishes when its leaders are in harmony with the Dao. However, Confucianism and Daoism are in disagreement about how communities and governments can keep in harmony with the Dao and, thus, promulgate different ideas about how to attain virtue. A painting of a person Description automatically generated[Confucius](https://commons.wikimedia.org/wiki/File:Half_Portraits_of_the_Great_Sage_and_Virtuous_Men_of_Old_-_Confucius.jpg). In Half Portraits of the Great Sage and Virtuous Men of Old (Yuan Dynasty) via Wikimedia Commons. This work is in the public domain. Confucianism is the social and ethical system set down by Kongzi (Master Kong) (c. 551-479 BCE), known in the West as Confucius. Kongzi saw the virtuous person as an artistic creation achieved through the diligent practice of ethical excellence by way of strict ritual practice. Ritual, or *Li*, is the art and practice of crafting one's character from the raw material of human nature. Just as a craftsperson uses tools to fashion wood or stone, a person uses ritual behaviors to carve and polish his or her character. *Li* extends to all aspects of life; Kongzi taught that our every action affects our character and our environment, so every activity needs to be performed with the proper respect and procedures. Kongzi issued hundreds of rites in sayings covering many aspects of human life, how youth should behave toward their parents, what colors of clothing one should wear and when, how one should greet another person, protocols that should be observed at the court of the ruler, and so on---all to be strictly observed in order to cultivate the comprehensive ethical virtue known as *Ren*. Most of the rites specified by Kongzi concern human interactions, reflecting the great importance he placed on suitably respecting one's superiors. Ancient Chinese society was highly stratified, and Kongzi thought that maintaining the social hierarchy was essential to social order. Showing respect for one's superiors, such as government officials, elders, and ancestors, was more than polite; it was essential for society to function properly. Filial piety was more than respecting your family elders dead or alive; it was the fundamental building block of social harmony and justice. The more one practiced the rites, the more one developed virtue, most importantly the virtue of *Ren* or benevolence. *Ren* should be understood not as acts of kindness but as acts of propriety that create virtue in oneself and society. Practicing the rites virtuously brings each person and society in harmony with the Dao and leads to a good life for all. The philosophy of Daoism has long provided a strong counterpoint to Confucianism. As the name implies, Daoism focuses on harmony with the Dao rather than on human teachings, the opposite of the Confucian emphasis on a system of ritual behavior. Daoist ethics centers on the fundamental virtue of *wu wei*, meaning "effortless action." Daoism rejects formal ritual and deliberately striving for virtue, emphasizing instead that virtue comes from naturalness, simplicity, and spontaneity. Daoism at times seems to be anti-civilization with its calls for us to detach from the artificiality of social traditions and rituals and to adopt instead a quiet life communing with nature. At other times, though, Daoism attempts to reform society, especially its leaders: If you want to be a great leader, you must learn to follow the Dao. Stop trying to control. Let go of fixed plans and concepts and the world will govern itself. The more prohibitions you have, the less virtuous people will be. (Laozi \[ca. 400-250 BCE\] 1991, Chapter 57) The Daoist idea is that separating ourselves from nature is separating ourselves from the Dao and that what most contributes to this separation from the Dao are the social institutions of government, military, and other social hierarchies and power structures. The Daoist virtue of *wu wei *involves a life of walking away from the artificial trappings of human pretension and arrogance and shaping your actions according to what others think of you. Instead, a Daoist seeks a oneness with the rhythms of nature, which probably requires walking away from society itself. Deliberately, Daoism does not provide a set of rules and rituals because central to Daoist philosophy is the idea that ritual does not cultivate virtue. Instead, Daoism provides guidelines on cultivating the virtues of selflessness, moderation, detachment, and humility. Accordingly, Daoist philosophers did not publish books detailing ritual practices like Confucians did. Instead, Daoists created poetry and stories that show Daoist sages teaching about and exemplifying these virtues. Objections to Virtue Ethics There are two main objections to virtue ethics as an ethical system: its vagueness and its relativism. First, virtue ethics is too vague and subjective, and does not produce explicit rules for moral conduct that can tell us how to act in specific circumstances. When facing ethical dilemmas, we feel better if we have a clear answer about what to do. Virtue ethics offers general ideals rather than definitive commands. We can create laws based on a definitive ethic against stealing, but we cannot make laws saying "be wise" or "be patient." Also problematic is that virtue ethics tends to hold that its virtues apply variably according to the situation. It is far easier to practice the principles of never lying or always being generous. Virtue ethics says there are times when lying is a better course of action and being generous is a worse course of action, and this variability creates uncertainty. What is more, how can I decide when the virtue applies and when it should not? Telling me to be wise and reflect on the ethical virtues and the situation is offering more vagueness. Finally, we want to be able to rely on other people's behavior, and those who practice virtue ethics may vary in their behavior, so we may not know exactly where we stand with them. To consider this objection, we need to think about the nature of ethics itself. Yes, we could say definitively, "You should not lie" and "you should not steal." But what are those prohibitions based on? A virtue ethicist could respond by arguing that both are based on the ethical principle of honesty and that if that is so, then cultivating the virtue of honesty will lead one not to lie or steal from others. A virtue ethicist would also say that virtue ethics focuses on the foundation of ethical life encapsulated in objective reason (Aristotle), God's natural law (Thomas), the law of karma (Buddhism), or the Dao (Confucianism or Daoism), and therefore virtue is not entirely variable. Virtue ethics provides us with the tools to make ethical decisions in the varying circumstances of our daily lives. The variability in the behavior of those who practice virtue ethics reflects the variability of everyday life. Second, there are different cultural definitions of human flourishing and virtue. All human cultures have ethical values, but values vary across cultures. So how can we decide which set of virtues is right? Even within a culture, two people will have different views about what the virtues are, and when and how they apply. Because virtue ethics gives us no specific commands for how to act, each person is left to himself or herself to decide how to act. Virtue ethics is too relative to be a helpful ethical theory. Ethical relativism is a concern. If ethics means anything, it has to have some objective basis and cannot be left entirely up to arbitrary whim. Virtue ethicists are aware of this danger and would respond to it that virtue ethics is based on objective realities of the world and human nature. The virtues are manifestations of how things are, or should be, outside of cultural or individual subjectivity. Different cultures differ on how ethical virtues should be applied, but every culture values fundamental virtues such as honesty, benevolence, courage, and justice. Differences in how cultures apply virtues may reflect objective differences in their circumstances. When we interact with another culture, those differences do need to be dealt with, but saying our culture is completely right and the other culture wrong is not a helpful approach. Individuals similarly face the burden of needing to determine how best to apply the virtues, and needing to deal with conflicts with others over how they think is best to apply the virtues. But is this not similar to the decisions we have to make in all aspects of our lives? Introduction to Virtue Ethics : Lecture Notes In the first module, we introduced ethics and got a first sense of what ethics is all about. In Module 1 I also discussed some skeptical approaches to ethics. Relativism is skeptical about the possibility of doing ethics because it says that there are no ethical truths: rather, ethics is just about what a culture or group thinks (cultural/popular relativism) or what the individual chooses and believes (individual subjectivism).  However, a lot still remains to be clarified about what ethics actually is. In this course, we are going to consider three different understandings of what ethics is all about. First, in Unit 1 (which you\'re starting right now), you\'ll be studying approaches to ethics on which ethics is a matter of becoming a good person and living a good human life. This probably isn\'t what you expected when you signed up for this course: my guess is that most of you expected the course to be focused primarily on the main question of Unit 2, which is \"How should we act?\" However, more ancient (and arguably non-Western) understandings of ethics tend to start with a different question: what is a good life? In other words, this more ancient understanding of ethics views ethics focused on helping us to live good lives, and perhaps become good people.  After we wrap up Unit 1, in Unit 2 we\'ll shift to thinking about ethics as about figuring out rules and principles to guide your action. Finally, in Unit 3, we\'ll consider ethics as the thing that enables us to live together cooperatively. The diagram below outlines what we\'ll study in this course in the list of items under \"ethics.\"   Before proceeding, please watch the following \[required\] video that introduces Unit 1. It\'s short! And there\'s a surprise guest.    Virtue Ethics We already know that Unit 1 is going to be about becoming a good person and living a good human life. In particular, in Unit 1 we\'re going to study a theory about ethics known as \"virtue ethics.\"  Virtue ethics can take a number of different forms (and we\'ll be briefly looking at how virtue as it is understood in a couple of different cultural contexts), but the thing that defines virtue ethics is, no surprise, a focus on developing virtue *in order to* live a good human life. The rest of Module 2 will expand on this theme, but in these lecture notes, we\'ll be dealing with the idea of virtue.  Two Senses of \"Virtue\" You probably all have an intuitive sense of what a virtue is. However, one thing we do a lot in philosophy is pause to investigate a seemingly intuitive concept in order to get a more accurate and nuanced understanding of it. Sometimes when you pause to think about a concept, you realize that you don\'t understand it nearly as well as you would have guessed! One thing to point out from the get-go is that we use \"virtue\" in two different senses.  1. Global Sense: makes an overall evaluation, i.e. \"that person is fully virtuous\" 2. Particular sense: refers to a particular trait, i.e. \"They are not kind, but wow, they have the virtue of courage.\"  As you can see from my examples, it\'s possible to have a particular virtue but not be overall, globally virtuous. But if you have virtue in the global sense, that means that you have a number of particular virtues. What is a virtue?  With that distinction set aside, let\'s try to get clearer on what a virtue is. What would you say: a character trait? A skill? A good feature?  In order to get clearer on what a virtue is, let\'s compare and contrast virtues with the following list:  1. Phsyical appearance 2. Tastes and preferences 3. Personality traits 4. Habits 1: The first item is perhaps easiest. Is virtue a kind of **appearance**? Obviously not. Virtue is something inner, something about one\'s character. Physical appearance has nothing to do with our character or our moral excellence. Furthermore, there\'s anotther important point of difference: although we are increasingly able to alter our appearance as new products and techniques are developed, these things aside, our physical appearance is largely genetic. In other words, we don\'t blame people or hold them accountable for how they look, because we understand that how a person looks is largely genetic and not under their control. However, at least according to Aristotle, we DO blame people and hold them accountable for lacking virtue.  2: What about **tastes and preferences**? By tastes and preferences, I just mean what a person likes and enjoys. At first, it seems pretty clear that virtue is not a taste or preference, because many tastes and preferences are morally insignificant. For instance, I am a person who often dislikes loud music. You will never find me attending packed concerts for fun, since I find such environments a sensory overload, extremely stressful and overwhelming. My husband on the other hand loves loud music and this kind of environment. However, this difference between us is morally insignificant. Neither one of us is a \"better person\" because we do or don\'t like loud music and crowds.  However, things get more complicated when we broaden the definition of tastes and preferences to include what brings us pleasure. Consider someone who takes pleasure in helping others on one hand, and someone who takes pleasure in cruelly teasing animals (say by throwing rocks at them). Is this a matter of virtue? Aristotle would argue that this is absolutely relevant to virtue. For Aristotle, moral virtue (roughly, a disposition to have the right emotions and in turn choose the right actions) are very much concerned with what brings us pleasure. The virtuous person takes pleasure in the right things. The vicious person doesn\'t.  3\. The idea of \"**personality traits**\" is a pretty modern one. By \"personality trait,\" I have primarily in mind things like extroversion and introversion (concepts that would probably be foreign to Aristotle). Although a lot of \"personality tests\" are [not grounded in scientific evidence at all Links to an external site.](https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/how-accurate-are-personality-tests/)(sorry, spoiler alert, everyone\'s favorite Myers-Briggs has no real scientific backing at all), there is some [scientific evidence that people really can be analyzed in terms of 5 personality traitsLinks to an external site.](https://psychcentral.com/lib/the-big-five-personality-traits#the-big-5-personality-traits), including for example introversion and extroversion (although being an extrovert or introvert is more like a sliding scale \-- it\'s not an on/off switch).  So is this kind of trait \-- for example being an introvert, or an extrovert \-- the same kind of trait as a virtue?  I would argue that there\'s not a direct correlation. I don\'t think it\'s true that introverts are automatically more virtuous, or extroverts automatically more virtuous. However, I do think people might be gravitate more readily to particular virtues on account of their personality traits. For instance, someone who is introverted may find certain virtues easier to acquire and certain vices more of a struggle, and the same for extroverts. We\'ll talk more about the idea of virtue as a mean below, but we can imagine that introverts might struggle with one vice and extroverts struggle with another vice, for instance.  4\. Finally, what about **habits**? You might pause here to brainstorm some habits.  Habits can range from the extremely mundane (the route you take to get to work or school each day, what you do before bed each night) to the life-changing (beginning each morning with prayer, meditation or reading; habits around exercise and social connection, etc). Clearly the habit of using mouthwash before bed isn\'t a moral virtue, but other habits sound more like virtues. For instance, someone with the habit of giving money to anyone in need sounds a bit virtuous, whereas someone with a habit of constantly interrupting others may need to work on virtues involving respect.  Virtue ethicists have a range of views about the relationship between habit and virtue \-- some strongly emphasize that virtue is a kind of habit (even if not all habits are virtues), whereas others put less emphasis on it.  At the very least, virtue ethicsts tend to emphasize that our habits are important in terms of developing virtue: Aristotle famously says that acquiring a virtue requries a good deal of practice, and so if we want to acquire a virtue, we must make it a habit to behave in the way a virtuous person would. So for instance, if we want to become generous, Aristotle would say that we must habitually behave like a genereous person.  Can I just give you a definition of virtue?  One thing you will quickly discover is that philosophers disagree on a lot of things. Some of you will find this maddening, because you want to be given neat and tidy definitions, but I think it\'s fun to discuss and debate as opposed to me having you all memorize a definition. So instead of wrapping up the above discussion by giving you a definition of virtue, I\'m going to give you four different definitions of virtue, and you\'ll get to compare and contrast these definitions.  1. Aristotle\'s Definition: \"Virtue, then, is a state of character concerned with choice, lying in a mean, i.e. the mean relative to us, this being determined by a rational principle\" (*Nichomachean Ethics *II.6 (1107a1)).\* 2. A definition from a textbook titled *Ethics for Life*: "A moral virtue is an admirable character trait or disposition to habitually act in a manner that benefits oneself and others" (Boss 384).   3. The definition from your textbook: "A virtue is a character trait. It's not a mere habit, or a tendency to act in a certain way. \[...\] Virtues require wisdom about what is important, and why. In addition to routinely acting well, the virtuous person also has a distinctive set of perceptions, thoughts, and motives" (Shafer-Landau 262).  4. From the [Stanford Encyclopedia of PhilosophyLinks to an external site.](https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/ethics-virtue/): \"A virtue is an excellent trait of character. It is a disposition, well entrenched in its possessor --- something that, as we say, goes all the way down, unlike a habit such as being a tea-drinker --- to notice, expect, value, feel, desire, choose, act, and react in certain characteristic ways" (Hursthouse & Pettigrove).  Look at these four definitions: what do you notice in common? What differences do you notice? Which definition to you prefer, and why? (\*Note: the definition from Aristotle is probably confusing to you; keep reading for an explanation about what it means.)  Unpacking the Definitions You\'re probably able to understand definitions 2-4 above pretty easily, but \#1 needs some clarification. First, I want to make a quick distinction between moral and intellectual virtues, since Aristotle divides virtue into moral and intellectual virtues. The definition above is a definition for **moral virtue, **sometimes also called \"virtues of character.\" What\'s the difference between these? Virtue most simply is a perfection or excellent, for Aristotle, so intellectual virtues are excellences in the part of our soul that engages in reasoning. (Or, if more modern terms, intellectual virtues are excellences in reasoning.) Intellectual virtues then get subdivided further into exclllences in reasoning about what\'s true (theoretical reasoning) and excellence in reasoning about how to act (practical reasoning).  Intellectual virtues are super important, and furthermore they are important for acting correctly insofar you have to reason well about how to act in orrder to act well. However, for no particular reason (limited time!), we are not going to talk about intellectual virtues. We\'ll focus our attention on moral virtues.  The first part of Aristotle\'s definition of moral virtue is relatively clear: \"a state of character.\" We probably have a pretty good rough sense of what this part means.  But what about \"concerned with choice\"? By this, Aristotle means several things. - One implication of this is that virtue is something you choose. Unlike hair texture, personality traits like introversion & extroversion, athletic skill, or genetic health conditions, virtue is something you actively choose, practice and learn. Why does he think this? Because we praise and blame people for virtue. If you have virtue, we give you moral praise. If you\'re not virtuous \-- if you\'re vicious \-- then we morally blame and criticize you. But it\'s not fair to praise or blame someone for something over which they have no control, i.e. things they were born with.  - However, another thing \"concerned with choice\" means is that **virtue itself is a kind of choice**.  In order to understand what this latter point means, consider two different people who both do something generous.  - The generous child: a child knows they are supposed to help people in need because their parents have told them this many times. They help a friend who\'s hurt because they know they\'re supposed to act in a kind and generous way.  - The generous adult: this person understands generosity from the inside. They are generous because they recognize that it is good to be generous and kind.  Aristotle would say that the latter person is deliberate choosing generosity for itself. The first person, the child, is simply acting generous and doesn\'t have the virtue of generosity. However, Aristotle nonetheless thinks that a habit of generosity is essential to becoming an adult who actually has the virtue! So it\'s not that the child is bad, according to Aristotle, it\'s just that they are still growing up and they have not yet fully acquired the virtue.  Lying in a Mean There\'s one further key point we need to unpack in Aristotle, and that\'s the idea of \"lying in a mean.\" In this context, he means \"mean\" as in \"average\" \-- you might have learned that an average is called a \"mean\" in math class. So on his view, virtue is an average or balance between two vices, one being a vice of deficiency (not having enough of the virtue) and a vice of excess (having too much of the virtue).  Courage is an easy-to-see example of this: not having enough courage = cowardice, and being disposed to feel way too much fear and run away from anything that seems remotely dangerous. Having too much courage = rashness or brazenness, and not having appropriate fear towards genuinely dangerous things.     Rejecting One-Size-Fits-All Moral Rules The idea of virtue lying in a mean has an important implication for Aristotle: he\'s not interested in spelling out a bunch of rules that we should follow. This is part of why this class is separate out into different units. In unit 2, we\'ll ask \"How should we act?\", but Aristotle would totally reject the idea that what we do in ethics is create a list of rules that tell us how to act. He thinks things are often much messier and we need to be people of good judgment and discernment - people with *phronesis*, or practical wisdom - in order to know how to act.  Let me give you a practical example that I face as a teacher: it is very hard to create a rule for attendance in my face-to-face classes. I have to take into account a lot of different things:  - It\'s really important for students to attend class - However, students sometimes have really good reasons for missing class, and sometimes they have a good reason to miss class and yet they don\'t have \"proof\" or \"evidence\"  - Furthermore, if students are constantly sending me evidence and I\'m constantly asking for evidence, it\'s very chaotic and overhwelming for all of us So if I create a rule \"No excused absences; you must always be present\" I create a problem with the second consideration. But if I create a rule \"You\'re an adult; attendance is up to you\" then I have a problem with the first consideration. In fact, it was really tricky for me to come up with an attendance policy that emphasizes how important it is to attend class but also honors the fact that students may have other things going on in their lives. I did end up coming up with an attendance policy, but I was half tempted to say \"No! I refuse! Determining when a student should be allowed to miss class is actually a matter of *phronesis*, a matter that requires good judgment and discernment, and I can\'t give a one-size-fits-all rule.\"  However, be careful: you might be tempted to take the idea of a mean and conclude that Aristotle doesn\'t believe in any universal moral rules. (\"Universal moral rule\" just means a moral rule that applies to everyone regardless of circumstance.) But Aristotle denies this. He says there are some things one must never do \-- for example stealing, and committing adultery. These aren\'t actions that we need to do according to the mean, in the right way and the right amount \-- Aristotle says they\'re actions that are just off the table, period.  What is a virtue? : Take II At this point I\'ve thrown a lot of ideas at you and you might be feeling a bit confused. If you\'re confused, that\'s probably a good sign, because that hopefully means you\'re thinking, and there\'s a lot to think about here. But if you need something to ground you, let\'s come back to the following ideas about (moral) virtue and what it is:   - Virtue is a state of character. - Virtue makes us excellent, good or admirable. - Virtue is acquired through habit and practice. It is not something we are automatically born with. - Virtue involves action, but it also encompasses or motivations, perceptions, emotions and desires. 

Use Quizgecko on...
Browser
Browser