Theories of Intergenerational Justice: A Synopsis PDF
Document Details
Uploaded by OpulentAntigorite9813
Universität St. Gallen (HSG)
A. Gosseries
Tags
Summary
This document provides a synopsis of various theories of intergenerational justice. It explores different philosophical frameworks regarding intergenerational responsibility and sustainable use of resources. Concepts discussed include indirect reciprocity and mutual advantage.
Full Transcript
S.A.P. I. E N.S 1 2008...
S.A.P. I. E N.S 1 2008 ISSUE Introduction Theories of intergenerational 1VOLUME justice: a synopsis A. Gosseries Permanent Research Fellow, Fund for Scientific Research (FRS-FNRS), Chaire Hoover d’éthique économique et sociale, 3, Place Montesquieu – 1348 Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgium ’’ Correspondence to: A. P. Gosseries, [email protected] In this paper, the author offers a synoptic view of different theories of intergenerational justice, along Abstract two dimensions (savings/dissavings) and three modalities (prohibition, authorisation, obligation). After presenting successively the indirect reciprocity, the mutual advantage, the utilitarian and the Lockean approaches, special attention is given to the egalitarian theory of intergenerational justice. Two key differences between the egalitarian view on intergenerational justice and the sufficientarian interpretation of sustainability are highlighted. Keywords: generations, sustainable development, just savings, indirect reciprocity, lockean proviso, Brundtland, Rawls, justice TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. Introduction 2. Tool box 3. Indirect reciprocity 4. Mutual advantage 5. Utilitarianism 6. Lockean Proviso 7. Rawlsian Egalitarianism 8. Egalitarianism revisited 9. Brundtland's Sufficientarianism 10. Conclusion "(…) as though man were never alone, as though he had inherited substance and strength, a gift which he must in turn hand on, through a being or an action”. (Márai, 1993: 164) 1. INTRODUCTION raised by environmental and resource depletion problems. Emphasis on the long term, the concept of pollution and the We have been facing threats to our environment and the risk issue of externalities are potent challenges to our attempts of depletion of natural resources for a very long time. To at articulating equitable rules for individual behaviour and such an extent, that they even appear to be determining social organisation. Simultaneously, new concepts are factors in the decline of certain civilisations. One of the constantly emerging from political and scientific debate, explanations given for the collapse of the Easter Island civil- such as "sustainable development", "ecological debt", isation is resources overexploitation (See e.g. Ponting, 1993; "degrowth" and "ecological footprint" (See e.g. Maréchal & Diamond, 2005). Lead poisoning, which is very ancient, is Quenault, 2005 on the former). They represent as many invi- said to have contributed to the fall of Rome (Gilfillan, 1965; tations to revisit de novo the nature of normative issues at Lessler, 1988; Bränvall et al., 2001). Despite technological stake. In order to do that, these emerging concepts must be progress, we remain highly dependent on our environment retranslated every time into the specific language of each as well as on natural resources. The scale and the nature of theory of justice. Otherwise, it would be impossible to link these issues have admittedly evolved over time. Yet, our environmental and natural resources issues with all the philosophical theories on justice fall astonishingly short of other societal challenges we simultaneously have to cope expectations in attempting to deal with the normative issues with in today's world. Received: 7 March 2008 - Accepted: 20 April 2008 - Published: 15 May 2008 Edited by G. Mainguy © Author(s) 2008. This article is distributed under the Creative Commons Attribution 3.0 License. www.sapiens-journal.org 61 A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS The concept of sustainable development is extraordinarily major kinds of intergenerational injustice that we propose to fashionable. There is no doubt that a requirement for inter- highlight. It is up to readers to consider whether the generational justice constitutes one of its key components. intuitions relating to justice that they would endorse in the In fact, its most popular definition is development that intergenerational context are consistent with the intuitions "Meets the needs of the present without compromising the to which they would be committed with respect to similar ability of future generations to meet their own needs (WCED, problems in a strictly intragenerational setting. 1987: 53). Yet, despite the degree of sophistication in evidence elsewhere in theories of justice, discussions on 2. TOOL BOX sustainability devote too little attention to a thorough exam- e need ination of what intergenerational justice might actually In view of the scale of environmental issues, it could be very mean. We must, however, underline that several other tempting to postulate at the outset that unprecedented TIEFto normative dimensions should also be considered so as to deal exhaustively with environmental matters. Firstly, conceptual challenges should be associated to them, requiring a complete revision of our general theories on justice. We can- epics issues of international or interspecific equity are crucial not exclude that this might well be the case. However, we Schinter also. But local justice (in the geographical sense) or gender intend to work from the opposite assumption and to begin by ererational issues cannot be neglected either. For some of the environ- using as best we can available conceptual resources before Justice mental challenges, these dimensions are even more exploring whether anything remains unaccounted for, requir- significant in practice or conceptually more challenging than ing the use of a radically new approach. To use an analogy, the intergenerational dimension in isolation. before coining new words or inventing a new language, let us see whether an existing language—in this case theories of jus- Furthermore, as we are focusing on the notion of sustain- tice—painstakingly constructed by successive generations of ability, it is essential to differentiate two issues: "Should “it” practitioners does not already provide sufficient vocabulary to endure, and if so, why?" and "Since it probably will endure, deal with the issues in hand. how should we go about making sure to do so equitably?". There are different ways in which a layman can be intro- We can reply to the latter question while sticking to an duced in a reasonably intuitive fashion to intergenerational agnostic stance on the former question. This in no way equity issues. One of them is to refer to rules for the use of means that we are denying the importance of considering common spaces by successive users. Consider the the very possibility that we might all decide to cease having metaphor of the uninhabited mountain hut. We can take a children, and to think about its meaning. This hypothetical certain number of rules commonly found posted in this kind situation raises several issues. For example, the very fact of refuge and use them as points of departure for general that human reproduction would then cease implies the theories. The following could be compared: "Please leave end—a voluntary end in this case—of the human species. the premises clean", "... as clean as you would have liked to Would the actions leading to such an outcome have to be find them on arrival" or "... as clean as they were when you considered immoral? Hans Jonas' thoughts are often arrived". All of these are starting points for theories of referred to as being central, although we are not in fact intergenerational equity based on different logics and with a inclined to consider that his characterisation of the alleged different content. immorality at stake here is entirely plausible (Gosseries, 2004a: pp8-22). Furthermore, the hypothetical case of gen- Another possible point of entry consists in envisaging the eralised refusal to have children also puts us in the situation nature of our intergenerational obligations through the of a "last man" which invites reflection on the moral status prism of concepts of private law, focusing specifically on the of non-human animals (see e.g. Gosseries, 1998: pp401-05). idea of property as well as on specific types of contracts. Consider the famous native American saying: “Treat the We should therefore remain aware of the specific niche of Earth well: it was not given to you by your parents, it was the intergenerational dimension so that we do not attempt loaned to you by your children. We do not inherit the Earth to force into the subject problems which would best be from our Ancestors, we borrow it from our children“. It analysed from other angles. Furthermore, if we focus on the refers to a loan contract, the next generation being the intergeneration issue, it is essential to compare the treat- lender and the current one the borrower. This is not the only ment proposed for environmental problems with what existing proposal. Burke (1790) refers in general terms to would be proposed for other matters which are just as the idea of a partnership “Between those who are living, important for intergenerational equity, such as public debt those who are dead, and those who are to be born”. The management, funding of pension schemes or passing on a Pennsylvanian constitution (art. 1, § 27) uses the idea of language. This paper aims to demonstrate that justice common property. Locke (1690 (2003): First Treatise, § 88) between generations can be understood in different ways refers to an idea of joint possession at the overlap. The and that some are more robust than others. It also aims to Japanese constitution uses the notion of an intergenera- explain why sustainable development as defined in the tional trust (art.XX). Jefferson (1789) claims that “The earth Brundtland report (WCED, 1987) is unable to exclude two belongs in usufruct to the living”. And Jaurès (1902) even 62 S.A.P. I. E N.S A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS worked out a concept of “everlasting mortgage”. We should justifying the preservation of biodiversity, or selecting a not exclude that lessons may be learned from a closer look funding scheme for the dismantling of our nuclear power at the potential and limitations of each of these proposals. stations (see respectively: Gosseries, 2006b; 2004a: pp241- Note that once such a full conceptual clarification has been 65; 2008). On the other hand, intergenerational justice also made, it will be useful to re-translate such findings in the raises the issue of our obligations to past generations. This specific language of general theories of justice. dimension, which we are also not intending to broach in this paper, is present at several levels, including in some the Using the mountain hut metaphor or referring to various theories presented below. It is also particularly relevant for kinds of contracts or types of rights in rem are helpful forms specific environmental issues, such as the integration of of introduction to the subject. Yet, they are only partially past CO2 emissions in the definition of the current share of illuminating. The approach we intend to use here will be con- obligations to reduce emissions (see Gosseries, 2004b). That structed a little differently. It will compare different philosoph- being said, let us now consider the crux of the matter. ical theories of justice along two lines. Firstly, only the size of the basket to be passed on to the next generation will be of 3. INDIRECT RECIPROCITY concern, not its composition. This basket is filled with the components which make up a capital, in the broadest sense One theory, discussed in particular by Brian Barry (1989), is of the word. Such capital is not only physical, but also techno- the indirect reciprocity theory (see de Shalit, 1995: pp96-99; logical, institutional, environmental, cultural, relational, etc. Gosseries, 2006a). The general idea of reciprocity We will therefore propose a table to summarise the key-con- presupposes that in the event people are able to do so, they clusions of each of these theories, based on two concepts: are under an obligation to return to others what they generational savings and dissavings. Savings occur (genera- themselves have received from them. In the case of tionally speaking) when one generation transfers to the next a intergenerational justice, one can assume that the idea of capital (in the extended meaning of the word) which is greater reciprocity is sociologically widely endorsed in the public than the one it inherited from the previous generation. (see Wade-Benzoni, 2002). In its "descending reciprocity" Inversely, there are generational dissavings whenever one version, it breaks down into two maxims. The first one seeks generation transfers to the next a capital which is smaller to explain why we are obligated to the next generation. In than the one it inherited. We will then go on linking these two this case, it is because we received something from our concepts (savings/dissavings) to three modalities: authorisa- parents that we must transmit something “in return” to our tion, prohibition and obligation. children's generation. The intuitive idea can then be accounted for in certain ways in the language of property or This approach may seem both desperately simplistic and more directly as reciprocation for an effort on the part of our excessively quantitative. And yet, the use of the parents. But this differs for example from the idea that if we savings/dissavings concepts—on top of the fact that they owe our children anything, it is because in fact we are only refer to a very broad understanding of the word "capital"— borrowing what already belongs to them. It also differs from first of all seek to highlight how much the various theories egalitarian logic as we shall see. Regarding the second of justice, as applied to the intergenerational realm, differ maxim, it defines the content of our obligations to the next from each other both in terms of rationale and of practical generation. As a result, we find: implications. Furthermore, we certainly do not deny the importance—and the possibility—of a debating on the Descending reciprocity different contents of the basket to be passed on from one generation Justificatory maxim: The current generation owes something to the next. This would require more than just weighing the to the next generation because it received something from the ways to pass things an in significance of environmental assets and comparing them previous one. itcouldals way with other requirements, such as those connected to the Substantive maxim: The current generation must pass on to be bad forthe transmission of special cultures or the preservation of the next a capital at least equivalent to the one it inherited from future mechanisms of solidarity. Even among the environmental the previous one. questions themselves, selections are also to be made between, for example, dams generating green energy and For those who associate justice with reciprocity, indirect endangered species, between preserving areas in their reciprocity is quite a potent idea. It has the advantage of natural condition and human intervention to save certain justifying obligations to people who so far have never given us species that are to be found there, etc (see Gosseries, 1997). anything and who may be giving us less in the future than what we will have given them. In the case of direct reciprocity, it is Finally, two further points should be noted. On the one hand, the original benefactor who ends up getting back what he put since the present paper is intended to provide a synopsis, we in, whereas with indirect reciprocity, there is a third party who will not be proceeding with a detailed examination of more benefits (in this case: the next generation) instead of the initial applied issues where intergenerational justice matters, benefactor (in this case: the previous generation), giving rise in such as defining the level of a global cap on CO2 emissions, this way to a chain of obligations. An obvious objection could be 63 A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS that a simple donation cannot in itself justify a return an intragenerational context. Take for example the case of a obligation. However, the nature of the moral difficulty arising person with multiple congenital disabilities. Let us accept the out of non-reciprocation in this case can be accounted for idea that she will give us less in return for what we as a society through reference to the idea of a free-rider, getting a free ride gave to her—which is not meant to deny the benefits we may on the intergenerational railway without buying his ticket, and of course derive from her company. Given such an example, therefore taking advantage without any counterpart of the the limitations of the idea of reciprocity are clear. As regards sacrifices made by all the preceding generations. so why would thepresent justification, is it because that person (or someone else) gave generationinvestinthen (or will give) us something that we feel obliged to care for this What are the obstacles in the way of the indirect descending dependent person as a matter of justice? The reply is probably reciprocity view? Firstly, if we refuse to dissociate the existence negative for many of us. And on the substantive side, should I of an obligation to the initial benefactor and that of an measure the dimension of what I owe this disabled person on obligation to the third party beneficiary, the justificatory maxim the basis of what he or she gives me in return? Here again, the presupposes the idea that we have obligations to past answer will be in the negative for many of us. This suggests generations, i.e. to the dead. It is in fact those obligations which that for many of us, over and beyond internal consistency are the source of our obligations to the next generation. difficulties, the idea of reciprocity is not fully capable of However, for a state to justify its sustainable development reflecting intuitions of justice in general and in the policies by reason of obligations to the dead is a challenge to intergenerational context in particular. the liberal requirement of neutrality on the part of the state towards various metaphysical conceptions and views of the 4. MUTUAL ADVANTAGE good life. It can be demonstrated that such obligations to the dead only make sense if it is postulated that the dead do exist The idea of mutual advantage is not very distant from that of in a sense that is morally relevant. Yet, we do not all subscribe reciprocity. Yet, it is not identical, both in logic (what justifies to this postulate, which makes it difficult to see it as the existence of obligations) and by its demands (for instance, metaphysically unproblematic (Gosseries, 2004a: chap. 2). the idea of guaranteeing the promised transfers between actors in a cooperative game). Briefly, a theory of justice Moreover, the justificatory maxim fails to justify the first—be it based on the idea of mutual advantage has to show that a hypothetical—generation’s intergenerational obligations, “rational” agent—i.e. one acting exclusively out of self- occurred because by definition such a first generation did not receive interest—will serve his best interest by engaging in a ready anything from a previous generation. How could we then cooperative venture and submitting to certain social rules 1 one one explain what the problem would if a first generation were to accordingly. The point therefore is to demonstrate that it is age in the squander from the outset a considerable part of the capital rational—in a narrow sense—to be fair and that rules of front available to it? For that matter, were we to view each justice must be justified by reason of rationality—in this same generation as a first generation insofar as the goods it invented narrow sense. In practice, this requires the demonstration or discovered are concerned, it would become immediately that gains may result from cooperation between individuals apparent that the present difficulty is necessarily devoid of and that these gains can make every one of us net practical implications. beneficiaries of such cooperation. A few other points could be mentioned such as the difficulties In an intergenerational context, we therefore need to check encountered by the substantive maxim in case of demographic how the idea of cooperation can be transposed. A key difficulty fluctuations. It should also be underlined that descending in this respect is related to the issue of intergenerational indirect reciprocity is not the only possible form of the idea of overlap (Gauthier, 1986: chap. IX–6). The fact that not all reciprocity in the intergenerational realm. For the sake of generations are—not even temporarily—contemporary is a comprehensiveness, let us also point at the ascending indirect challenge on two counts. Firstly, does this not threaten the reciprocity idea (relevant for example to explain the logic of very possibility of the benefits of cooperation being mutual? pay-as-you-go retirement schemes) as well as at the double Because if benefits are real but are only in favour of certain reciprocity concept (Cosandey, 2003) which involves direct generations, so that others are net contributors, a theory of reciprocity transfers between generations. However, these mutual advantage would be incapable of justifying that all two alternative forms of intergenerational reciprocity are not generations should submit to a common rule of justice. directly relevant to the environmental field which constitutes Replying to this question amounts to asking to what extent the our focus point here (Gosseries, 2006a). possibility of descending benefits (from one generation to the next) and ascending benefits (from one generation to the In any event what really matters in this context, is to emphasise previous one) depends on these generations overlapping with the need to check whether indirect reciprocity really reflects one another. Furthermore, not only must it be possible for our intuitions about justice, both intergenerationally and as a benefits to be mutual, but there must also be a guarantee that component of a general theory of justice. The simplest method the conditions exist for the rule of cooperation to be effectively for such a purpose consists in testing the idea of reciprocity in respected by each generation. In this case again, the non- 64 S.A.P. I. E N.S A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS contemporary nature of many generations in respect of each savings (in generational terms) are not just authorised; they other challenges the possibility of enforcing respect of a given are required since the goal is to maximise the size of the rule of intergenerational transfer. The degree to which a intergenerational welfare pie. This means that the first threat of ascending or descending sanctions can remain generations in history have to tighten their belts and invest credible in the absence of intergenerational overlap therefore for the benefit of future generations. A point worthy of remains to be ascertained. mention is that the idea of productive investment, which is central to this theory, is not necessarily linked to the number This twofold challenge is compounded by a further question: of generations following us—at least for investments whose supposing it is possible to construct an intergenerational return does not depend solely on human activity, but rather model in such a way as to successfully address this challenge, to the fact that they will be arriving after us. there will still be a need to verify what that implies in relation to our question on savings and dissavings. It would be This result leading, in a way, to sacrificing the earlier perfectly possible to imagine that it is rational for each generations is magnified by two extra—and independent— generation to submit to a rule, which would nevertheless be factors. On the one hand, it is realistic to postulate some compatible with a gradual deterioration of the stock of intergenerational altruism due partly to the fact that the resources transferred by each generation to the next. There is succession of generations is also linked to biological parent- an ongoing debate on this point (Heath, 1997; Arrhenius, to-child relations which inevitably generate a certain degree 1999), but it has not reached a point where clear conclusions of altruism. It is also plausible to postulate that this altruism can be drawn (see Gauthier, 1986: pp302-05). It is however is asymmetric, being stronger from parent to child than obvious that any serious attempt at articulating a theory of from child to parent. If such a descending altruism is taken justice from the angle of mutual advantage cannot elude an into account, an extra degree—and in this case a purely in-depth examination of such difficulties. voluntary one—of saving may be added to the obligation to save referred to above. In other words, descending altruism 5. UTILITARIANISM could further intensify the generational savings trend already present in the utilitarian model. Nevertheless, it does not Let us now explore a very different theory: utilitarianism. It necessarily lead to an additional welfare differential if the is characterised not only by its preoccupation with people's actors themselves derive well-being from these altruistic acts. welfare (utilitas in Latin) but more particularly with the idea On the other hand, the utilitarian conclusion becomes more that a fair organisation of society is one which maximises worrying if it is accepted that the number of coming the aggregate welfare of its members (See e.g. Smart & generations is, if not infinite, at least indefinite. For one way of Williams, 1973). This is why we can refer to it as an interpreting utilitarianism consists in forcing us into aggregative theory. There are several unsound reasons for everlasting sacrifices, since there is no way of knowing where criticising utilitarianism. Yet, it is entirely true that this they should stop. Such a sacrifice would ultimately be to no theory of justice is not primarily concerned with the one's benefit, since every generation would be obliged to save distribution of welfare among the members of society. What given the permanent uncertainty as to how many generations matters is the size of the welfare pie from which society as would follow. if therewould be more and more theres no a whole will benefit, not the relative size of the pieces of that sense to invest in them pie each member will be receiving. Hence, sacrificing Utilitarians are well aware of this problem. Let us therefore entirely the well-being of a few people (to the point for emphasise two factors pointing in the opposite direction. example where they are reduced to slavery) making it Firstly, a factor which could attenuate the scope of the possible to maximise society's well-being as a whole (by the obligation to save is diminishing marginal utility, a (fairly fact that a large portion of society would benefit from the plausible) postulate traditionally referred to as a justification slavery imposed on a tiny minority), could be the policy for aggregativists’ concern for the distribution of levels of well- advocated by utilitarians in specific circumstances. being (see Gauthier, 1986: 305). The underlying idea is that the Therefore, more than any other theory of justice, this one is more a person has of a given good (e.g. apples), the less an likely to lead to sacrificial consequences, although in its additional good will bring her additional utility. This means that more elaborate versions, it does try as best it can to avoid if we have an extra apple, it should be given to the one who has such counterintuitive outcomes. less apples if we aim at maximizing the additional welfare generated by this apple. But more importantly, there is In an intergenerational context, there is one fact that plays a another idea, the one of a social discount rate. This has been crucial role in this respect. Giving up the consumption of the subject of extensive philosophical debate for decades (see part of our capital today may enable us—provided it is wisely e.g. Cowen & Parfit, 1992; Birnbacher, 2003). And one recent invested—to consume much more of that capital at some instance is to be found in the discussions surrounding the more or less distant future time. Consider a bag of seeds, Stern report on the economics of climate change (Stern, 2007). part of which could be either consumed immediately or The idea is simple: if the rate is positive, a unit of future welfare sown so as to multiply its volume. If you are a utilitarian, will be granted less value than the same welfare unit produced 65 A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS today. A discount rate of this kind can meet certain concerns generally right-wing people, arable land initially does not besides addressing the single "sacrificial" issue mentioned belong to anyone, hence the use of the first come, first served above. For example, it would be possible to give a lower principle. For others, generally more left-wing, the initial status discounted value to a future welfare unit because of the of external resources would be that of collective property, which uncertainty as to its actual future existence. However, when it would explain the need for respecting a Lockean proviso. One is simply a question of a pure time preference for the present, difficulty is that the idea of a Lockean proviso is interpreted in it becomes morally problematic once applied to relations different ways, depending on whether Nozick's views or those between different individuals (rather than to merely planning of others are adopted (Vallentyne & Steiner, 2000). What did the welfare profile within one’s own existence). In fact, the idea Locke really mean when he said that initial appropriation can be can be put forward that at that level it is still only an attempt— legitimate "At least where there is enough and as good left for an ad hoc (Rawls, 1999: 262) and rather ineffective one—to others” (Locke, 1690: second treatise, §27; Waldron, 1979)? Let reduce the size of a problem—i.e. an inclination toward us be more direct in our formulation: "At least where there is as sacrificing earlier generations—which is in fact the logical much which is left in common for others". Applied to the outcome of utilitarianism. intergenerational domain, this could give us for example Arneson's formulation: "The continued legitimacy of private ownership from Even if descending altruism is left aside, the conjunction of the standpoint of self-ownership depends on each successive recognising the productive nature of capital (whenever generation obtaining the equivalent of a per capita share of properly invested) and the indefinite nature of the number of unimproved, undegraded land" (Arneson, 1991: 53). future generations is such that, in the intergenerational context, utilitarianism can lead to particularly sacrificial A libertarian theory wishing to apply such a Lockean proviso outcomes, albeit attenuated by the inclusion of diminishing will first of all need to determine its content ("as much as marginal utility as well as the introduction of a social discount what?") and apply it specifically to the intergenerational rate. The reason why such outcomes seem especially context (see Elliot, 1986: 217ff.; Arneson, 1991: pp52-53; unacceptable to many of us probably has to do with the fact Steiner, 1994: pp268-73; Wolf, 1995: 791ff.). Let us outline that our conception of justice generally involves a distributive three versions applicable to the intergenerational domain. A motive besides or instead of an aggregative one. first possible interpretation is: each generation should leave to the next at least as much (or the equivalent) of what the first 6. LOCKEAN PROVISO (prehistoric) generation initially appropriated for itself. For those who consider that the basket of goods inherited from the Before examining the paradigmatic example of a distributive immediately previous generation exceeds far and away the theory of justice — Rawlsian egalitarianism — let us consider value of what the prehistoric generation would have had yet another family of theories. This time, it is neo-Lockean access to, this formulation of the proviso may appear too lax. rather than neo-Hobbesian, and is commonly referred to as For it would authorise the entire generation to dissave, libertarianism. Briefly, libertarian views are building on two inasmuch as the resources transmitted in fine to the next core features: On the one hand, a definition and a strong generation are in no way less substantial, as regards their protection of self-ownership; on the other, a particular way of productive potential, than the resources available to the (first) broaching the subject of ownership of external resources—in prehistoric generation. In effect, that formulation could be contrast to internal resources which are part of self- amended in two ways. ownership. In this way, libertarians aim at guaranteeing, both against state and third party intervention, a strong protection The first consists in taking into account the natural for people's physical integrity as well as e.g. for the ownership modifications of our resources as time goes by. Let us imagine of their talents. What is of particular interest here, however, is that the generation before us was the first to be victim of a the status of external resources. We need in this respect to minor ice age which will continue for two generations. Ex determine how to allocate to members of society the property hypothesi, this overall has a negative impact (as regards land of the goods we have inherited. productivity, biodiversity, etc.). Should the present generation compensate for the difference — originating in natural events Consider a first generation allocating the property of arable — between the value of the prehistoric world and what it has land. Some libertarians would incline to allocate ownership of in effect become due to natural circumstances? For a Lockean, such property on the basis of a rule of the "first come, first there is no particular reason why this should be so. What served" variety, which for that matter is a rule in use in various matters as a reference scenario to implement such a Lockean sectors of society, for instance as regards intellectual property proviso, is to be able to identify what other people's situation rights. Others would have us subordinate legitimacy of would have been in my absence — in this case, the situation of appropriation to complying with so-called "Lockean" provisos. any previous generation if it had been the first. The following In general, the difference between those two major approaches alternative formulation therefore seems commendable: each will reflect, coexist with or result in differences in perceptions of generation must leave to the next at least as much as what the the initial patrimonial status of external resources. For some, next generation could have appropriated in the absence of any 66 S.A.P. I. E N.S A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS previous generation, or preferably1, what the coming are concentrating here on possible differences between "at generation would otherwise have inherited if no previous least as much as what prehistoric generations had", “at least generation had by its actions brought about a net as much as what G+1 would have had in the absence of any improvement or a net deterioration. earlier generations” and "at least as much as G+1 would have inherited in the absence of G only". And the specificity of the Let us however imagine a hypothetical situation where some Lockean approach is to focus on the question of knowing to of the previous generations — and not this time natural what extent my existence deprives someone else of something disasters — had damaged, without any compensating he could otherwise have benefited from. technological improvements, the state of external resources difficult compared to what they would have been if left to the sole effect 7. RAWLSIAN EGALITARIANISM of natural causes. Using the above proviso, there would be an obligation to save. Now why should the current generation Rawls, in his masterpiece "A theory of Justice" (1999: §44), is bear the cost of compensating for deteriorations brought aware of utilitarianism’s major difficulties in the about by the activity of previous generations and for which they intergenerational context. At the same time, he considers that are in no way responsible, or at least no more so than the moving away, be it minimally, from the initial condition of coming generation in whose favour it seeks to meet its prehistoric men is necessary, not just for reasons of efficiency, obligations? Conversely, for those who consider that the but even for reasons of justice. How can both these concerns cultural capital inherited from our ancestors considerably be accommodated? By defending a "two-stage" model in increases the productive potential of natural resources which which a steady state phase follows an accumulation phase. the next generation would have inherited in the absence of any During the accumulation phase, principles are identical to previous generation, the degree to which such a formulation those of utilitarianism (compulsory savings). But this phase is authorises anew a very significant margin of dissavings supposed to have a limited duration. And the rationale becomes apparent. underlying the need for such accumulation is totally unrelated A further reformulation of the Lockean proviso is however with maximising the size of the intergenerational welfare pie. possible: each generation must leave to the next at least as For Rawls, the aim of the accumulation phase is to allow much as what the next generation could have appropriated if economic affluence to build up so that at least minimal stability the current generation had not contributed by its action to a to just institutions can be ensured. As soon as this point is net improvement or deterioration of what the following reached, accumulation ceases to be an obligation and the generation would otherwise have inherited. This third steady state phase begins. And for that second phase, the interpretation takes into account not just the natural principle defended by Rawls is identical to the one defended by improvements or deteriorations that have occurred since the indirect reciprocity view. prehistoric times. It also includes the accumulated product of the physical and intellectual activities of the generations which Like Rawls, we believe that such a "two-stage" approach is preceded the current one. The only thing we need to do then is necessary. We also believe that he is justified in defending the to consider what would have been the situation of each principle of an obligation to save during the accumulation generation in terms of external resources (both natural and phase (for a full discussion: Gaspart & Gosseries, 2007). cultural), not in the absence of all previous generations, but However, this second thesis is not self-evident. What is rather in the absence of the single preceding generation. potentially shocking for an egalitarian like Rawls, is to propose for the accumulation phase a principle of compulsory savings In the language of savings and dissavings, that means that that goes against a concern for the worst off. In fact, from this savings are authorised, whereas such a Lockean proviso in no viewpoint it is unfair, strictly speaking, to demand savings from way authorises dissavings, unless the environment which the the first generations. Doing so would bring about an next generation will inherit has deteriorated compared to what intergenerational world where the least well off are not as well we ourselves inherited, for reasons unrelated to our own activity off as they could possibly be. Merely sticking to a prohibition on (i.e. natural events or resulting from the activity of previous dissavings would not have such consequences. Rawls is aware generations). This implies, for example, that any climate change of this problem but still insists on an obligation to save. Let us resulting from strictly historical emissions (i.e. resulting from attempt a brief defence of Rawls' position the principle our ancestors' activities only, not from ours) and which would applicable to the accumulation phase. lead to a worse climate for the next generation than for our own, would not imply for us any specific obligations – which by the His theory is not just egalitarian, it is also liberal but in a very way shows that the question of historical emissions raises not specific sense which must not be confused with its usual just transgenerational equity issues (Gosseries, 2004b), but meaning in the designation of certain political actors on the also issues relating to intergenerational equity. While what European political arena. It is liberal in the sense that pursuing would be defended in this case by a proponent of indirect the improvement of the situation of the least well off must be reciprocity is not entirely clear, the egalitarian view would done within the constraints we refer to as "basic liberties". In clearly differ here from the Lockean one. Be that as it may, we other words, defending those few basic liberties (physical 1 I owe this improved formulation to P. Vallentyne 67 A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS integrity, freedom of speech, etc.) takes priority over the We cannot go into the details here of this rather counter- objective of improving the social and economic condition of the intuitive principle, or which at least seems to be so at first sight underprivileged. It could then be said that the reason why a (for a more extensive defence: Gosseries, 2004a: chap. 4; violation of the egalitarian objective is allowable in the Gaspart & Gosseries, 2007). But we must emphasise that even accumulation phase, has to do with the aim of setting up as if such an approach is not totally incompatible with the idea of quickly as possible institutions which could then be able to growth, it should certainly be contrasted with other ideas in the defend personal basic liberties and that this latter objective "anti-growth" family of arguments (see Gosseries, 2004a: takes priority over the former. Now, if we can demonstrate that pp224-25, Gaspart & Gosseries, 2007). Among these, let us the richer (in terms of GDP) a democratic State becomes, the mention four, all different from the one defended here. The more likely are its chances of retaining its democratic first consists in stating that growth, in so far as it would lead to character, we are in possession of an empirical argument able increased inequalities internationally, would be unfair in this to support the claim that setting up equitable institutions respect. The second underlines that the adoption by a State of requires a certain level of affluence. Although we can agree a policy to encourage economic growth is contrary to the with the "two-stage" theory and with the principle Rawls principle according to which the State should remain neutral defends for the accumulation phase, we believe that an as regards people's varying concepts of what the good life upholder of equality of opportunity should be defending a should be (Bonin, 1997). The third states that growth is futile, if different principle in the steady state phase. And what principle not counter-productive, from the point of view of really should that be? worthwhile conceptions of the good life. A fourth argument considers that growth, in so far as it mobilises large amounts 8. EGALITARIANISM REVISITED of physical resources, would not be sustainable at the current rate. Each of these four arguments deserves closer scrutiny, We do not believe that Rawls is entirely true to the demands of both on their factual assumptions and their normative egalitarianism in the steady state phase. We consider that plausibility. However, it should be stressed that prohibiting dissavings should go hand in hand with prohibiting intergenerational egalitarianism as developed here presents savings. This may sound absurd. Is it at all unfair for parents to an argument which differs from those, notwithstanding the voluntarily scrimp and save to provide a better life for their fact that it does refer to a concern for justice as do the first two children than the one they could have had themselves? Who "anti-growth" arguments outlined above. could the victims of such allegedly unjust behaviour be? The answer to this question is that the victims would be the least It is also clear now that the conclusions of an egalitarian theory well off members of the generation of such parents. Let us do not converge, in the steady-state phase, with those of for consider the situation of a generation anticipating that, at the instance, indirect reciprocity. Furthermore, there is another end of its existence, it might have transferred a surplus to the significant angle from which the proposed convergence is next generation in comparison with what it had received from absent. This becomes clearly apparent if we consider a future the previous generation. The theory we are defending here is natural phenomenon (e.g. an earthquake) negatively that it should not be the next generation taken as a group that impacting the fate of the next generation. From an intra- should be benefiting from this surplus, but rather the least generational point of view, a destructive earthquake must give well off members of the current generation. To transfer a rise to compensation from those who did not suffer its effects, surplus into the future sacrifices to the same extent today's so as to mitigate as much as possible, the negative least well off. It is only if each generation adheres to the consequences for the unlucky few of a phenomenon they were principle of prohibiting both savings and dissavings that the not responsible for. For a luck egalitarian, any disadvantage intergenerational world that we will build can be seen as one arising out of circumstances beyond people's control should µ where the least well off, regardless of the generation to which give rise to compensation from the rest of society. A congenital they belong, will be better off than they would have been in any handicap or a particular mother tongue are characteristics other alternatively organised world. Note that this prohibition which are unquestionably circumstances affecting those on savings has nothing to do with a preference for the concerned. A luck egalitarian would immediately add however members of our own generation. It is derived from a that if disadvantages arise out of people's own choices, their generational impartial concern for improving the situation of costs should be borne in principle by the very people who the least well off, whichever generation they belong to. made such choices. The debate in France on local mountain Admittedly if this surplus were passed on to the next communities having to foot the bill for rescue missions to save generation, it could well benefit the least well off members of people practising dangerous sports, or the debate in Austria that generation. But what we would have to make sure of is concerning the non-reimbursement of hospital expenses for that the least well off members of our own generation would alcoholic coma induced by particular drinking habits in the not end up then in a worse situation than the one experienced younger population, clearly point in the direction of practices by the least privileged of the next generation. which could well be viewed by an egalitarian as the result of a choice. In such cases, it would not be society's duty to shoulder the burden of its cost (on choice/circumstance: Dworkin, 2000). 68 S.A.P. I. E N.S A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS How can we transpose this choice/circumstance distinction Let us be quite clear: this is not an internal criticism of into the intergenerational field? Let us go back to our previous Brundtland's theory. Furthermore, if space permitted, we example. If we were able—by extraordinary means—to predict could certainly try and demonstrate with far greater subtlety the occurrence and magnitude of such future earthquakes and the extent to which Brundtland's report probably opens the if we were able to demonstrate that the next generation will be way to alternative interpretations. Nevertheless, what is of particularly affected by them although, we, the current importance here, is that those who consider that luck generation, would not be affected in the slightest, the current egalitarianism is the most plausible theory of justice when generation would then be under a savings obligation so as to dealing with intragenerational allocation issues have no ensure that, as a result of these earthquakes, the next reason to abandon this theory when moving on to generation does not find itself in more unfavourable intergenerational issues. Egalitarians should certainly reject circumstances than the current one. This obligation to save Brundtland's theory as being insufficient. arises out of a very different logic from one based on utilitarianism or the one included in the accumulation phase of 10. CONCLUSION the egalitarian theory. But above all, it does not seem for example, that an indirect reciprocity approach could ever This short paper is based on a set of simplifying assumptions. compel us to transfer more to the next generation than what We did not, for example, consider the composition of the we received from the previous one. basket of goods to be transferred to the next generation (e.g. can the oil or the biodiversity that we are squandering be 9. BRUNDTLAND'S SUFFICIENTARIANISM replaced by motorways or cultural assets?). We only broached on a very general level the issue of equitable intergenerational We are now well prepared to support the assumption that transmission, on the basis of two categories Brundtland's definition of sustainable development would not (savings/dissavings) and three modalities (prohibition, be a sufficient safeguard for intergenerational justice. As authorisation and obligation). Nevertheless, this synopsis has mentioned above, development is only said to be sustainable if allowed us to highlight two important points. Firstly, using a it "Meets the needs of the present without compromising the very simplified framework, one can see in outline some very ability of future generations to meet their own needs" (WCED, different operational principles. We can observe for example 1987: p53). Contrast this formulation with Daly's, according to that both the utilitarians and the egalitarians (in the which "... the basic needs of the present should always take accumulation phase and in certain limited assumptions in the precedence over the basic needs of the future but the basic steady state phase) include the generational savings obligation needs of the future should take precedence over the in their theories, albeit for very different reasons. We can also extravagant luxury of the present" (Daly, 1996: p36). see that the dissavings prohibition option is to be taken Brundtland's reference to the concept of need can admittedly seriously by egalitarians in the steady state phase. Finally, are be understood in its broader or narrower meaning. To our also worth noting the departures from the dissavings mind, the most appropriate interpretation is that of "basic prohibition that are present in the Lockean or sufficientarian needs". But even with a less restrictive version, there is still in approaches. Secondly, it is now obvious that the standard such a definition the idea that once everyone's needs are approach to sustainable development as Brundtland views it is covered, fairness does not require any further redistribution. by no means the only option. And it is clearly problematic on As long as everyone's basic needs are covered, this two counts for an egalitarian. "sufficientarianism" based on the satisfaction of needs would In point of fact, these theories of justice provide resources for not demand, for example, that a person born with a missing thinking not just along different lines, but also for broaching finger due to genetic malformation, should be receiving the issue of intergenerational justice through the prism of compensation if that missing finger does not prevent him from various logics which, if they are understood in depth, can satisfying his basic needs (on sufficientarianism: Casal, 2007). generate a multiplicity of implications. This is particularly true once the ultra-simplified world represented here is enriched In the view of a luck egalitarian, the residual injustice following with a set of additional variables to bring it closer to the real Brundtland's sufficientarianism in that case, is twofold. First, it world. Each of these theories can respond differently for authorises a possibly significant degree of dissavings as long example to demographic fluctuations, the case of the indirect as it is compatible with the capacity of the next generation to reciprocity view being probably the most emblematic on this provide for its own needs. Second, by authorising generational count. For certain theories, population changes would modify savings—that is as long as it does not compromise the what we owe to the next generation, whereas for others, it capacity of all the members of the current generation to satisfy would in no way alter the magnitude of our intergenerational their own needs, it is not responding to the egalitarian obligations. Similarly, the degree to which descending requirement for prohibiting savings on principle out of concern intergenerational altruism turns out to be significant will for the least well off in our own current generation. affect, to a greater or lesser degree, our obligations to the next generation depending on the theory which is adopted. Generational overlap (or its absence) is also more significant in 69 A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS TABLE 1: Synopsis of the various intergenerational theories of justice some approaches than in others, particularly in the case of mutual advantage theories. And the fact that a previous Bonin P.-Y. (1997). Neutralité libérale et croissance generation has, or has not, fulfilled its own obligations (non- économique. Dialogue, 36, 683–703. compliance issue) will affect, also in varying degrees, the obligations that each of these theories places on the current Bränvall, M.-L. et al. (2001). Four thousand years of generation. It is illuminating in this regard to have in mind how atmospheric lead pollution in northern Europe: a summary a Lockean proviso tackles the disregard, by a generation from Swedish lake sediments. J. Paleolimnol., 25, 421–435. previous to our own, of its intergenerational obligations; and how an egalitarian theory can take on board the risk of non- Burke E. (1790). Reflections on the French Revolution. The compliance with its intergenerational obligations by one of the Harvard Classics Vol.24 part3. generations that comes after us. http://www.constitution.org/eb/rev_fran.htm As we can see, taking the standard theories on justice seriously is fairly enlightening as to the various possible ways Casal P. (2007). Why Sufficiency is Not Enough. Ethics, 117(2), of tackling the issue of our intergenerational obligations. To be 296–326. sure, there is still a long way to go before we can define the precise contours of these obligations... and set up the Cosandey D. (2003). La faillite coupable des retraites. institutions to enforce them. Comment nos assurances vieillesse font chuter la natalité. Paris, L’Harmattan. Ackowledgements This paper is a revised version of Gosseries (2005). We Cowen T. & D. Parfit, (1992). Against the Social Discount Rate, particularly wish to thank B. Gagnon, M. Fleurbaey and P. in: Justice between age groups and generations. edited by: Savidan for their comments during the preparation of this Laslett, P., and Fishkin, J., New Haven/London, Yale University paper, the original French version of which is forthcoming in Press, 144–161. Raison publique (2008). We are also much grateful to Evelyn Apaire Van Gelder for her translation from French. Daly H. (1996). Beyond Growth, The economics of sustainable development. Boston, Beacon Press. REFERENCES De Shalit A. (1995). Why Posterity Matters. Environmental policies and future generations. London, Routledge. Arneson R. (1991). Lockean Self-Ownership: Towards a Demolition. Political Studies, 39(1), 36–54. Diamond J. (2005). Collapse. How societies choose to fail or survive. Viking Books. Arrhenius G. (1999). Mutual Advantage Contractarianism and Future Generations. Theoria, 65(1), 25–35. Dworkin R. (2000). Sovereign Virtue. The Theory and Practice of Equality. Cambridge/London, Harvard University Press. Barry B. (1989). Justice as Reciprocity. in: Liberty and Justice, Oxford, Oxford University Press. Elliot R. (1986). Future Generations, Locke’s Proviso and Libertarian Justice. Journal of Applied Philosophy, 3(2), Birnbacher D. (2003). Can discounting be justified? Int. J. 217–227. Sustainable Development, 6(1), 42–53. 70 S.A.P. I. E N.S A. GOSSERIES THEORIES OF INTERGENERATIONAL JUSTICE: A SYNOPSIS Gaspart F. & A. Gosseries (2007). Are Generational Savings Marai S. (1993). Les Confessions d’un bourgeois. Paris, Albin Unjust? Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 6(2), 193–217 Michel (Le Livre de Poche). Maréchal, J.-P. & B. Quenault (Eds.) (2005). Le développement Gauthier D. (1986). Morals by agreement. Oxford, Clarendon durable, Une perspective pour le XXIè siècle. Rennes, PUR. Press. Ponting C. (1993). A Green History Of TheWorld. The Gilfillan S.C. (1965). Lead Poisoning and the Fall of Rome. J. Environment and the Collapse of Great Civilizations. New York, Occup. Med., 7, 53–60. Penguin. Gosseries A. (1997). De la nécessité de distinguer protection de Rawls J. (1971). A Theory of Justice (revised edition). l’environnement, conservation de la nature et conservation de Oxford/New York, Oxford University Press, 1999. la biodiversité. Revue juridique de l’environnement, 22(2), 220–227. Smart J. J. C. & B. Williams (1973). Utilitarianism. For and Against. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press. Gosseries A. (1998). L’éthique environnementale aujourd’hui. Revue philosophique de Louvain, 96(3), 401–405. Steiner H. (1994). An Essay on Rights. Oxford, Blackwell. Gosseries A. (2004a). Penser la justice entre les générations. Stern, N. (2007). The Economics of Climate Change: The Stern Paris, Aubier-Flammarion. Review. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press http://www.hm-treasury.gov.uk/6520.htm Gosseries A. (2004b). Historical Emissions and Free-riding. Ethical Perspectives, 11(1), 36–60. Vallentyne P. and Steiner H. (Eds.) (2000). Left Libertarianism and its Critics: The Contemporary Debate. New York, Palgrave. Gosseries A. (2005). The Egalitarian Case Against Brundtland’s Sustainability. GAIA, 14(1), 40–46. Wade-Benzoni K.A. (2002). A Golden Rule Over Time: Reciprocity in Intergenerational Allocation Decisions. Academy Gosseries A. (2006a). Dette générationnelle et conceptions de of Management Journal, 45(5), 1011–1028. la réciprocité. in: Finances publiques et redistribution sociale, edited by: Pellet, R., Paris, Economica, 367–391. Waldron J. (1979). Enough and as Good Left for Others. Philosophical Quarterly, 29, 319–328. Gosseries A. (2006b). Egalitarisme cosmopolite et effet de serre. Les séminaires de l’IDDRI (Paris), 14, 18–23. WCED (1987). World Commission on the Environment and Development: Our Common Future. Oxford/New York, Oxford Gosseries A. (2008). Radiological Protection and University Press. Intergenerational Justice. in: Ethics and Radiological Protection, edited by: Eggermont, G. and Feltz, B., Louvain-la- Wolf C. (1995). Contemporary Property Rights, Lockean Neuve, Academia-Bruylant, Provisos and the Interests of Future Generations. Ethics, 167–195. 105(4), 791–818. Heath J. (1997). Intergenerational Cooperation and Distributive Justice. Can. J. Phil., 27(3), 361–376. Jaurès J. (1902). Etudes socialistes. Paris, P. Ollendorf http://gallica.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/bpt6k886633 Jefferson Th. (1789). Letter to James Madison (6 sept) http://odur.let.rug.nl/_usa/P/tj3/writings/brf/jefl81.htm Lessler L. (1988). Lead and Lead Poisoning from Antiquity to Modern Times. Ohio J. Sci, 88(3), 78–84. Locke, J. (2003). Two Treatises of Government and A Letter Concerning Toleration. edited by: Shapiro, I., New Haven/Londres, Yale University Press, 1690. 71